THIS "O-P BK" Is AN AUTHORIZED RK PRINT OF THK ORIGINAL EDITION, PRODUCED BY iMicROFiLM-XEROGRAPHv BY UNIVERSITY MICROFILMS, INC., ANN ARBOR, MICHIGAN, 196-1 DEONTOLOGY; OK, THE SCIENCE OF MORALITY: IN WHICH THE HARMONY AND CO-INCIDENCE OF DUTY AND SELF-INTEREST, VIRTUE AND FELICITY, PRUDENCE AND BENEVOLENCE, ARE EXPLAINED AND EXEMPLIFIED. J FROM THE MSS. OF JEREMY ^ENTRAM, """ ' — •-• > ^ ARRANGED AND EDITED BY JOHN BOWRING. IN TWO VOLUMES. VOL. I. LONDON: LONGMAN, REES, ORME, BROWNE, GREEN, AND LONGMAN. EDINBURGH: WILLIAM TAIT. 1834' H- i 9 2 s o v r; CONTENTS.— PART I. THEORY OF VIRTUE. \ PAGE PREFACE . . . . v to vi INTRODUCTION . . .1 — 6 CHAPTER I. eneral Statement . . .7 — 20 CHAPTER II. Deontology Explained . . 21 -p 37 CHAPTER III. Anti-Deontological Propositions removed— Summum bonum . . .38 — 58 CHAPTER IV. Pleasure and Pain — their relation to Good and Evil . . . .59 — 77 CHAPTER V. / Well-Being and Ill-Being . . . 78 — 82 CHAPTER VI. End of Action . . .83 — 86 CHAPTER VII. Sanctions . . 87 — 121 CHAPTER VIII. Causes of Immorality , . .122 — 131 CHAPTER IX. Analysis of Confused Phraseology, by the Deontological Test . 132—137 CHAPTER X. Virtue Defined . 138 — 155 VI CONTENTS. CHAPTER XI. PAGE Self-interest, or Self-regarding Prudence . 156 — 165 CHAPTER XII. Prudence as regards others, or Extra-regarding Prudence . . . 166 — 175 CHAPTER XIII. Effective JBenevolence,— Negative . . 176—187 CHAPTER XIV. Effective Benevolence,— Positive . .188 — 194 CHAPTER XV. Analysis of Virtues and Vices . .195 — 222 CHAPTER XVI. Tlume's Virtues . . . 223 — 258 CHAPTER XVII. False Virtues . . . 259 — 262 CHAPTER XVIII. The Passions . . . 263 — 270 CHAPTER XIX. Intellectual Faculties . . .271—275 CHAPTER XX. Conclusion of Theoretic Part . . 276 — 283 HISTORY OF THE GREATEST-HAPPINESS PRINCIPLE . . 287 — 332 PREFACE. THIS work was in the course of preparation for the press when its great Author's earthly labors were suddenly closed. He had, up to the latest period of his existence, been accustomed to re cord the desultory thoughts which occurred to his mind on the important subject of which the volume treats ; and I had the advantage, in my intimate communion with him, of seeking such guidance from him as was necessary for the understanding and arrangement of the mass of undigested fragments which he from time to time placed in my hands. It was a happy and an interesting task to follow him through those inves tigations in which benevolence aricJ wisdom were mutual handmaids, — and emphatic indeed was the instruction which was so beautifully exem plified in every thought, and word, and action of Vlll PREFACE. the Instructor. I took up my pen with alacrity — I pursued my task with ever-new delight— I end it with feelings of gloom, for which I can find no adequate expression. The charm is gone — the voice is silenced which conducted and gladdened me on my way. These pages as I turn them over seem to have the solemnity of a sepulchral echo. I shall find a fitter occasion for speaking of him who suggested them, who * was himself the virtuous man he drew/ — and I deliver them to the world, — my first offering in discharge of those duties which have devolved upon me as the legatee of those literary treasures which he, my Friend and Master, has confided to my keeping and to my care. J. Bo. INTRODUCTION. IP it be assumed that virtue should be the rule, and happiness the object of human action, he who shows how the instrument may best be applied to the production of the end, and how the end may be accomplished in the greatest obtainable degree, is undoubtedly engaged in the exercise and entitled to the recompense of virtue. /No small service will be done to man kind, if moral laws can be discovered suited to all the circumstances of life, — if the habitual power can be communicated to the honest inquirer of answering well and wisely that so often embarrasing question, which occurs to every one of us every day — every hour of our ex istence, — How shall I act? and why? The pages which I have the privilege of now intro ducing to the world, are calculated, I trust, to illumine the dark parts of the field of morals — VOL. I. B 2 INTRODUCTION. to unravel many entanglements, to solve many doubts, — and to contribute much satisfaction to the searchers after truth and virtue. The MSS. were put into my hands without reservation or restriction as to the manner of their publication. The extreme indifference of their extraordinary author to what is denominated literary fame, stands out in prominent: contrast to that anxiety which he has never hesitated to express, that his opinions might go careering through the world. He has always been rather desirous of digging out and refining the ore than of stamping it with his own ' image and super scription.' Not that futurity will forget its benefactor, or fail in honor due to him who must and will exercise a mighty influence on its condition. Of Bentham's writings, that may fitly be said which Milton proclaimed of one of his almost forgotten volumes, that it ' numbered high intellects/ Our author's doctrines have strongly moved the philosophic few, and their course is rapidly opening and widening down wards among the improving many. Scoffers may have insulted him in his progress, but INTRODUCTION. 3 where is the sage who has scorned, or who having listened has been wanting in reverence and gratitude to the man who first made legislation a science ? The course which Bentham has taken is to employ such language as would convey his ideas with the greatest precision to inquirers. A vague phraseology is necessarily the parent of vague ideas. In the minds of the well disposed it is a source of confusion — in the hands of the ill disposed, an instrument of mischief. Right and wrong — justice and injus tice, are terms susceptible of very different interpretations. They may be used — they have been used, according to the caprice or the selfish interest of men for the production alike of good and evil. When closely examined they will generally be found nothing more than the expression of the opinion more or less influential of him who employs them ; and their value and fit application will depend on their capacity to stand the test of some other principle. The language of common parlance must, before it can be made use of for the communication of 4 INTRODUCTION. correct ideas, be translated into the language of happiness and unhappiness — of pleasures and of pains. Into these elements all moral results ultimately resolve themselves. Here is a point beyond which there is no advancing. If there be a greater good than happiness, let him who has made the discovery produce it as a reward ; if there be a greater evil than misery, let its inventor employ it for the ends of punish ment. In the dictionary of pain and pleasure, our moralist has found all the machinery of his craft. Fiat experientia was the axiom of Bacon ; an axiom which has been recognized as the foundation of all genuime science. Fiat obser- vatio, is Bentham's apophthegm. What experi ment is to the philosopher, observation is to the moralist. Bentham has examined human actions through the pleasures and pains which are consequent upon them, and has grounded all his reasonings upon this examination. In such pursuit truth can hardly have escaped him; for truth and utility must go together hand in hand ; and he who discovers what is useful » INTRODUCTION. 5 cannot be far off from that which is true. It isf in fact, more easy to overtake truth by pursuing utility, than to reach truth at all without utility for a guide ; since that which is useful is matter of experience, while conjecture is busied in asking, What is Truth? To those who are acquainted with Bentham's 'Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation/ and who have pursued the train of reasoning there broughtforward, the present work may offer little that is new ; and perhaps there are some who will think its con tents have been already anticipated and its utility superseded by that masterly monument of analytical and logical power. But for universal acceptance the prin ciples therein lafd down assume too much the shape of axioms, and certainly wanted — as the inconsiderable circulation of the volume has evi denced — the attractions of popularity. \The pre sent work, whose especial object it is to approve itself to the general reader, is more desultory and diffuse, and seeks to win its way by a style less stern and severe. /The former was written for the meditation of the profound thinker 6 INTRODUCTION. —this looks to a wider and more popular, but less elevated sphere of usefulness. Besides, the 1 Introduction * has a more extensive and am bitious character, and is mainly occupied with a developement of the true principles of Legis lation, whose discussion, spite of its importance, can have few fascinations for mankind at large. In the volume before us it is not intended to enter ,on the inquiries of jurisprudential science. \Cur concern is with private morality, and that has a claim to the attention of every body, on every occasion in which thought, word, or action is engaged.") GENERAL STATEMENT. CHAPTER I. GENERAL STATEMENT — ALLIANCE BETWEEN INTEREST AND DUTY. HE who in a deliberative assembly volunteers to bring any motion forward, confers on himself a distinction, in which his prominency cannot but be contrasted with the equality of the rest ; — so, he who in the republic of letters chooses to range himself among the few who write, be comes necessarily contradistinguished from the many who read, and both speaker and writer take upon themselves no inconsiderable respon sibility. But, while in the case of a meeting for discussion, every impropriety of the speaker has the chance of immediate correction — in the case of that fictitious and never assembled body which creates the tribunal of public opinion, no instant removal of error has place ; — secured for the most part against contradiction, the public writer is liable to assume a confidence unwar ranted by his position. He has a motive to avoid giving to his doctrines and precepts the support of adequate reasons, the production of which would interfere with his love of case, and the 8 DEONTOLOGY. developement of which would demand an addi tional exercise of intellectual effort. The public legislator, with all his powers, is generally less despotic in his phraseology than the public writer — that self-constituted legislator of the people. He makes laws without giving rea sons, — laws which generally convey only his sovereign will and pleasure. It is indeed a misfortune that men come to the discussion of important questions, predetermined to decide them only in one way. They are pledged, as it were, to their own minds, that certain practices shall be wrong, and certain other practices right. But the principle of. utility allows of no such peremptoriness, and requires, before any prac tice is condemned, that it be shown to be dero gatory to human happiness. Such an investi gation suits not the dogmatical instructor. With the principle of utility", therefore, he will have nothing to do. He will have a principle of his own to do his own business. He will convert his own opinion into a principle for its own support. ' I say these things are not right/ he proclaims with a sufficient portion of positiveness — ergo, they are not right. It is plain this setting up of an opinion as the true foundation and sufficient reason for itself, must put every imaginable extravagance upon an equal footing with the most salutary persuasion ; GENERAL STATEMENT. 9 nor does it offer any other or better standard of right and wrong than the violence with which it urges its pretensions, or the number of those who agree in them. But if violence be the standard, as there is no possible way of measuring the intensity of conviction but by its visible in fluence on actions, — the opinion of him who knocks down his opponent is better grounded than that of him who only asserts his opinion vehemently, — of him who cuts his opponent's throat than of him who only knocks him down, — and of him who tortures before he destroys his opponent than of either ; so that, in truth, the opinions of the Inquisition bid fairest of any yet known for being the very perfection of truth and right reason, and morality may be gradu ated according to the miseries inflicted by per secution. If numbers decide, Idolatry would drive Christianity from the field, — and truth and morality would be in a state of everlasting vibration between majorities -and minorities, which are shifting with all the vicissitudes of human events. He who, on any other occasion, should say, ' It is as I say, because I say it is so/ would not be thought to have said any great matter : but on the question concerning the standard of mo rality, men have written great books wherein 10 DEONTOLOOV, from beginning to end they are employed in saying this and nothing elsej What these books have to depend on for their efficacy, and for their being thought to have proved any thing is, the stock of self-sufficiency in the writer, and of implicit deference in the readers ; by the help of a proper dose of which, one thing may be made to go down as well as another. Out of this assumption of authority has grown the word obligation) from the Latin verb, obligo, to bind, — while such a cloud of misty obscurity has gathered round the term, that whole volumes have been written to disperse it. The obscurity, notwithstanding, has continued as dense as before, and it can only be dissipated .by bringing in. the light of Utility with its pains and pleasures, and the sanctions and motives which spring out of them. It is, in fact, very idle to talk about duties ; the word itself has in it something disagreeable and repulsive ; and talk about it as we may, the word will not become a rule of conduct. \ A man, a moralist, gets into an elbow chair, and pours forth pompous dogmatisms about duty — and duties. Why is he not listened to ? Be- s cause every man is thinking about interests^ It is a part of his very nature to think first about interests ; and with these the well-judging mo- GENERAL STATEMENT. 11 ralist will find it for his interest to begin. /Let — him say what he pleases, — to interest, duty must;and will ,be made subservient.,/ To place prominently forward the connection between interest and duty in all the concerns of private life, is the object now proposed. The more closely the subject is examined, the more obvious will the agreement between interest and duty appear. All laws which have for their end the happiness of those concerned, endeavour to make that for a man's interest which they proclaim to be his duty. And in the moral field it cannot be a man's duty lo do that which it is his interest not to do./* Morality will teach him rightly to estimate his interests and his duties ; and examination will ^ show their co-incidence. That a man ought to sacrifice his interest to his duty is a very com mon position, — that such or such a man has sacrificed his interest to his duty is a frequent assertion, and made the ground-work of admi ration. But when interest and duty are consi dered in their broadest sense, it will be seen that in the general tenor of life the sacrifice of § interest to duty is neither practicable nor so much as desirable % that it cannot, in fact, have place ; and that if it could, the happiness of mankind would not be promoted by it. I It has been almost invariably the usage in treating of 12 DEONTOLOGY. morals to speak of a man's duty — and nothing more. Now, though it can scarcely be said with truth that what is not a man's obvious interest is not his duty, it may be safely pronounced^ i unlessitcan be shown that a particular action "or course of conduct is for a man's interest, the attempt to prove to him that it is his duty, will be but a waste of words. Yet with such waste of words has the field of Ethics been hitherto filled. ' It is your duty to do this — it is your duty to abstain from doing that;' and this is easy travelling for a public instructor. * ' But why is it my duty?' And the answer if sifted will be found to be, — ' Because I bid you — because it is my opinion — my will.' * Well, but suppose I do not conform myself to this will of yours?' ' O then you will do very wrong,' — which being interpreted means, ' I shall disapprove of your conduct/j \ It will scarcely be denied that every man acts with a view to his own interest — not a correct view — because that would obtain for him the greatest possible portion of felicity ; and if every man, acting correctly for his own inte rest, obtained the maximum of obtainable happi ness, mankind would reach the millenium of accessible bliss ; and the end of morality — the general happiness — be accomplished . To prove ^ > that the immoral action is a miscalculation of GENERAL STATEMENT. 13 self-interest — to show how erroneous an estimate « the vicious man makes of pains and pleasures, is the purpose of the intelligent moralist./ Un less he can do this he does nothing :— for, as has been stated above, for a man not to pursue what he deems likely to produce to him the greatest sum of enjoyment, is in the very nature of things impossible. The object, then, of these pages is to promote human happiness — the happiness of every man. Your happiness, reader, and that of all besides. It is to extend the dominion of happiness wherever there is a being susceptible of its impressions ; nor is the sphere of benevolent action bounded by the human race. For if the animals we call inferior have no title to our care, on what foundation stands the claim of our own species ? The chain of virtue will be found to girdle the whole of the sensitive creation — the happiness we can communicate to lower natures is intimately associated with that of the human race, — and that of the human race is closely linked to our own. It were, indeed, greatly to be desired that some benevolent moralist should take the animal creation under his patronage, and establish their claims to the protection of legislation and to the sympathies of the virtuous principle. Perhaps this event is hardly to be anticipated, while so 14 DEONTOLOGY. large a portion of the human race itself are excluded from the influences of beneficence — and treated like the inferior animals — not as persons, but as things. True, the animal tribes have little power to act upon human sensibilities — few means of inflicting misery as a punish ment for injustice and cruelty, and fewer still of recompensing humanity and beneficence by the communication of pleasure to man. We deprive them of life ; — and this is justifiable — their pains do not equal our enjoyments — there is a balance of good. But why do we torment, — why do we torture them ? It would be diffi cult to find a reason why law should deny to them its interference. The real question is — are they susceptible of pain? Can pleasure be communicated to them ? Who shall draw the line, — and where is it to be drawn between the gradations of animal life, beginning with man, and descending to the meanest creature that has any power of distinguishing between suffer ing and enjoyment? Is the faculty of reason, or that of discourse to determine ? ' But a full- grown horse or dog, is, beyond comparison, a more rational, as well as a more conversible animal than an iniant of a day, or a week, or even a month old. And suppose the case were otherwise, what would it avail ? The question is not, Can they reason? nor, Can GENERAL STATEMENT. 15 they talk? but, Can they suffer r — Introduction to the Principles of Morals, fyc. chap. xvii. p. 309. But, of sensitive beings, the human are the nearest and naturally the dearest to us. And how can their happiness be best provided for by you ? How but by the exercise of the virtues — of those qualities the union of which is virtue ? Virtue divides itself into two branches — prudence* and effective benevolence.f Pru dence has its seat in the understanding. Effec tive benevolence principally in the affections ; those affections which, when intense and strong, become passions. Prudence again has two divisions — that which respects ourselves, or the self-regarding,^: which * There is a narrow and exclusive meaning attached to the word prudence, and attached in a sense disassociated from any moral quality, namely, the apt application of means to an end. It is hardly necessary to say that it is not used in this confined sense here. f It has been necessary to create a compound, as no single word in our language conveys the idea of benevolence in a state of activity, or of benevolence and beneficence united. Benevolence without beneficence is a fruitless tree, adding nothing whatever to happiness; and beneficence apart from benevolence is no virtue; it is no moral quality — it belongs to a stock or a stone, as well as to a human being. J This is used instead of selfish, which conveys an idea of a vicious preference. • 1C DEONTOLOGY. might have been exercised by the prototype of Robinson Crusoe, Alexander Selkirk, in his uninhabited island ; — and that which respects others, and which may be denominated extra- regarding prudence. Effective benevolence is either positive or negative. Its operation is by action, or by abstaining from action. Its business is either with the augmentation of pleasure or the. dimi nution of pain. When it operates positively by the production of pleasure, power as well as will must be possessed. When it operates negatively by abstaining from action, nothing but the will is required. The power of benevo lent action is limited — the power of benevolent abstaining is unbounded ; and abstinence from action may involve a quantity of virtue or vice equal to that growing out of action itself. There are cases in which a man might as properly be punished for murder who had failed to do what lie was bound to do in order to prevent murder, as the actual murderer himself, jit is a sad reflection withal, that the quantity of happiness which any, even the mightiest, can produce, is small compared with the amount of misery he may create by himself or others.. Not that the proportion of misery in the human race exceeds that of happiness ; for the sum of misery being limited, to a great extent, by the GENERAL STATEMENT. 17 will of the sufferer, he possesses, for the most part, some power of relief. But the tendency of effective benevolence is to increase by exercise. The more we pour out its wealth upon others, the greater does the stock of wealth become which we ourselves possess. The diffusion of its riches is the very source of its opulence. He who secures for himself a pleasure, or avoids for himself a pain, influences his own happiness directly ; — he who provides a pleasure, or prevents a pain to another, indirectly advances his own happiness. ! What is happiness? It is the possession of pleasure with the exemption from pafy. It is in proportion to the aggregate of pleasures enjoyed, and of pains averted./ And [what is virtue ? It is that which most contributes to happiness, — that which maximises pleasures and minimises pains. Vice, on the contrary, is that which lessens happiness, or contributes to un- happiness. The first law of nature is to wish our own happiness; and the united voices of prudence and efficient benevolence, add, — Seek the happi ness of others, — seek your own happiness in the happiness of others.: Prudence, in common parlance, is the adapta tion of means to an end. In the moral field that end is happiness. The subjects on which pru- VOL. it. c 18 DEONTOLOGY. dence is to be exercised are ourselves, and all besides ; ourselves as instrumental, and all be sides as instrumental to our own felicity. \JTo_. obtain the greatest portion of happiness for him self, is the object of every rational being. Every man is nearer to himself, and dearer to himself, than he can be to any other man ; and no other man can weigh for him his pains and pleasures. Himself must necessarily be his own first concern . His interest must, to himself, be the primary interest ; nor, on examination, will this position be found unfriendly to virtue and happiness; for how should the happiness of all be obtained to the greatest extent, but by the obtainment by every one for himself, of the greatest possible portion?_/ Of what can the sum total of happiness be made up, but of the individual units ? What is demanded by prudence_and benevolence, is re quired by necessity. Existence itself depends for its continuance on the self-regarding principle.^ Had Adam cared more for the happiness of Eve than for his own, and Eve, at the same time, more for the happiness of Adam than for her own, Satan might have saved himself the trouble of temptation. Mutual misery would have marred all prospects of bliss, and the death of both have brought to a speedy finale the history of man. And what is the important deduction from GENERAL STATEMENT. 19 these postulates ? Are they anti-social in their consequences? Nay! they are in the highest degree philanthropic and beneficent. For^/how can a man be happy, but by obtaining the friendly affections of those on whom his happi ness depends ? And how can he obtain their friendly affections, but by convincing them that he gives them his own in exchange ? And how can he best convince them, but by giving them these friendly affections in reality; and if he give them in reality, the evidence will be folmd in his words and deeds. Helvetius said, that * in order to love mankind, we ought to expect little from them.' We must be moderate in our calculations — moderate in our exactions. Pru dence requires that we should not raise too high the standard of our hopes ; for disappointment will diminish our own enjoyments, and our good will to others : whereas the unanticipated ser vice done to us, coming with the charm of sur prise, will bring with it a grea4er sum of plea sure, and strengthen the benevolent dispositions in our relations with others. The principle of utility, then, in order to pre serve its influence, must be habitually kept in view; and to this end, in the expression of every maxim subordinate to it, let its relation to that principle be seen. Let it not be thought sufficient that the reason assigned for a practice is in itself 20 DEONTOLOGY. in conformity with an estimate of a supposed result of happiness, — or with a vague notion of some useful object to be accomplished ; but let such conformity be constantly dwelt upon, be brought forward for examination and approval and traced into all its consequences of future good and evil. This is the only expedient to prevent persons not sufficiently imbued with the principle— persons who have not climbed those heights on which utility has fixed its throne — from being led astray by the despotic dogma of asceticism, or the sympathies of a mis calculating and misdirected benevolence. Let the moralist regard the great Deontological Law, as steadily as the Turnsole looks upon the sun. DEONTOLOGY EXPLAINED. 21 CHAPTER II. DEONTOLOGY EXPLAINED — TERM WHY ADOPTED. DEONTOLOGY is derived from the Greek words, TO Seov (that which is proper) and Aoyia, know ledge — meaning the knowledge of what is right| or proper ; and it is here specially applied to ? the subject of morals, or that part of the field of action which is not the object of public legislation. As an art, it is the doing wl at is fit to be done ; as a science, the knowing what is fit to be done on every occasion. But the inquiry, as applied by the individual to his own rule of conduct, resolves itself into a question as to what he himself approves — what can be made to appear to himself as fit to be approved on the given occasion. And why should he declare his approbation of a particular course of conduct? Undoubtedly, because the approbation may lead to its adop tion. And it will be thus conducive to it. Public opinion is made up of individual opinions ; and public opinion is that which constitutes the' popular or moral sanction. A 22 DEONTOLOOV. large quantity of recompense to act upon our hopes, and a large quantity of punishment to influence our fears, are in the hands of popular opinion. [Of this influential power, every in dividual iiTffie community forms a part; and may exercise and apply his portion of reward or punishment, — reward for the acts which merit his approbation — punishment for those of which he disapproves. He has thus a power over motives, and that to the extent in which he can dispose of the matter of pleasure and pain. These motives may sometimes be brought into operation by merely indicating their ex istence ; at other times they may be created : and under both circumstances they will in fluence human conduct ; nor can the effect be always foreseen. The affections and the will are touched by the motives prescribed to them, just as the Eolean harp-strings vibrate to the passing wind. By presenting motives, we necessitate acts ; by awakening expectation of eventual pain or pleasure, we influence cha racter. In proportion to the confidence felt in the opinions and f->"d!y disposition of the teacher, will be the sh% fence of the learner; in proportion to the p?.in or pleasure excited by the disapprobation, or approbation, which the instructor may be able to attach to different actions, will be the power of the instructor to DEONTOLOGY EXPLAINED. 23 enforce or to prevent those actionsTJ And the test of the value of the worlc Tie~enters upon will be its harmony with some recognised principles, by which he consents that his in struction shall be tried. The business of the Deontologist is to bring forth, from the obscurity in which they have been buried, those points of duty, in which, by the hands of nature, a man's interests have been associated with his enjoyments, — in which his own well-being has been connected, com bined, and identified, with the well-being of < others ; to give, in a word, to the social, all the influence of the self-regarding motive. He < is to use, for the production of the greatest sum of happiness, those elements of happiness which exist in the breast of every man ; to extend the domain of felicity, by developing the principles which are co-extensive with the existence of man — the self-regarding prin ciples being necessarily, and happily, the strongest. For such an artist, there is no want of work, — there can be no want of work, while remediable evil is to be found in the world. His business is to establish his propositions, by bringing a balance of happiness, out of each of them, — a balance to somebody — a balance to the one, or to the many. The principle, then, on which Deontology is 24 DEONTOLOGY. grounded, is the principle of Utility ; in other words, that every action is right or wrong — worthy or unworthy — deserving approbation or disapprobation, in proportion to its tendency to contribute to, or to diminish the amount of public happines^ And that the public sanction will, in as far as the subject is understood, be given to that line of conduct, which most promotes the public happiness, is a corollary requiring no arguments for its establishment. Three very obvious inquiries grow out of these remarks, and will be constantly kept in view during the progress of our investigations. 1. What does the public happiness require? 2. Is public opinion in harmony with the public interest or happiness ; and 3, as the practical application, What line of conduct ought to be pursued in each individual case which presents itself for consideration ? The end being marked out, and acknowledged to be wise and good, it becomes the primary object to ascertain,] whether that end is best promoted by the opinions held, and the conduct pursued in accordance with these opinions ; • whether, in a word, what the world calls morality, is really that happiness-producing instrument which it ought to become. And the question must be asked, and the test applied, in every portion of the field of conduct. DEONTOLOGY EXPLAINED. 25 Morality, Religion, Politics, can indeed only have one common object. If the politician, moralist, and divine, all know what they are about, their purposes can be no other than the same. ^The politician's end is universally allowed to be happiness — the happiness of the state — the greatest happiness possible among the in dividuals of a state, during the present life, j To the politician, as such, licence is given to make this his end, by all parties, whatever may be their opinions on religion or morals, by all parties, without one dissenting voice. This being the case, it were strange if the ends of the other two were allowed to be differ ent. For were they so — if different and, upon occasion, opposite were pursued — if the Di vine and the Moralist contemplated results contrary to those intended by the Politician, they would be in a state of universal warfare. Each would be reduced, for his security, or for the furtherance of his end, to fight against the other two with such weapons as he is master of. The divine would denounce his antagonist to the vengeance of the Celestial Tribunal ; would imagine, or would forge decrees from it, and endeavour to persuade the by-standers to execute them. The moralist would thunder out the anathemas of his self-erected Court Moral, or, 26 DEONTOLOGY. as some affect to denominate It, common sense ; would call his enemy fool, and villain, and hypo crite, and nonsense- talker ; and make interest with the by-standers to treat him as if he were so. And the politician, if incommoded by such sort of artillery, would be driven to defend him self by such means as he is provided with. And, indeed, if things were to come to this, the politician would be found rather too hard for the other two ; and the upshot of the fray would be, did not his own principles, and the con sciousness of their value restrain him, that he would set his arms a-kimbo, and, like Lord Peter in the history, kick his obsteperous bre thren out of doors. Not that this is a conduct by any means to be recommended to him,* (though upon the score of what is commonly called justice, they certainly would have no reason to complain) because, if anything can be predicated of the future, it is that, in this coun try at least, such violence never can be needful, needful to his own purpose ; a purpose which this volume is intended to forward. Here no * The tranquillity and good temper of a disputant is in proportion to the inward consciousness of the aptitude of his arguments to produce conviction. Accordingly, mathema ticians, so long as they confine themselves within the pro vince of their science, cannot be, and accordingly never have been, otherwise than tranquil. DEONTOLOGY EXPLAINED. 27 lesfcon will be given which persecution is to enforce. It were better far to join the ranks of the antagonists ; for nothing is so likely to frus trate the ends of truth, as to league it with the infliction of useless suffering. This the Deonto- logist will not recommend to the Politician ; but what may be safely recommended to him (and it will be perfectly competent to the pur poses as well of punishment as of defence) is, to let the talkers talk on, and never to give himself any trouble about what they say. Let him but pursue his end industriously, and show that he pursues it, he need not fear but that in a free and enlightened country (indeed in any country, if he give such an example) the majority of the people will ultimately lend him their concur rence, and in the Deontologist he will find a mighty ally. The line which separates the dominions of the Legislator from those of the Deontologist is tolerably distinct and obvious. 'Where legal re wards and punishments cease to interfere with human actions, there precepts of morality come in with their influences. The conduct which is not given over to the tribunals of the state for judgment, belongs to the tribunals of opinion. ] There are a variety of acts in which judicial Lptfmshment would be unprofitably wasted, but which may be safely and properly transferred to 28 DEONTOLOGY. extra-official punitory visitations.) Of conduct injurious to the community, a large portion necessarily escapes the cognition and the visita tion of penal law, while it falls under the obser vation, and is submitted to the award of, the more extensive and penetrating cognizance of popular retribution. Thus the crimes which are recognised by the penal code, if they escape detection and punishment, whether from want of sufficient evidence, or any other cause, may be brought into the field of Deontology. But it is not of these that it is proposed to treat. It is desirable, no doubt, to widen the field of moral, and to narrow that of political action. Legisla tion has intruded too far into a territory which does not belong to it. It has frequently inter fered with actions, when its interference has only produced a balance of evil ; and, what is worse, it has interfered with opinions, particu larly on religious topics, where its interferences have been in the highest degree pernicious. In a word, Deontology, or Private Ethics, may be considered the science by which happiness is created out of motives extra-legislatorial — while Jurisprudence is the science by which law is applied to the production of felicity. The object of every man's wish and of every man's endeavour, from the beginning of life to the end of it, is to increase his own felicity: — DEONTOLOGY EXPLAINED. 29 his felicity — as connected with pleasure and disconnected with pain. But again what is pleasure — and what is pain ? Does every man form the same estimate ? Far from it. That is pleasure which a man's judgment, aided by his memory, recommends and recognises to his feelings as pleasure. LNo., man can allow another to decide for him as to what is pleasure, — or what is the balance or the amount of pleasure. And hence a necessary consequence, that every man of ripe age and sound mind ought on this subject to be left to judge and act for himself— and that the attempts to give a direction to his conduct inconsistent with his views of his own interest, is no better than folly and impertinence. / And the more closely the matter is examined the more de cidedly will this be found to be the case. The business of the moralist, what then does it become ? He can place before the eyes of the inquirer a sketch of the probable future more correct and complete than would have presented itself to his view in the midst of present influences. The moralist may assist him in making reflections and drawing con clusions — in taking a more comprehensive audit of the past, — and from thence deducing calcu lations or conjectures for the time to come. He may point out ends which had not suggested 30 DEONTOLOGY, themselves, — and means by which they can be accomplished. He may enable him to wisely choose between balancing pleasures or pains. He may mark out occasions where enjoyments may be reaped or sufferings avoided. And thus far he will be labouring in an honest and honourable vocation. In fact^jjojbe most useful he will be employed somewhat in the character of a scout — a man hunting for consequences — consequences resulting from a particular course — collecting them as well as he can, and pre senting them for the use of those who may be disposed to profit by his services. His task is humble — his labor is great — his reward can only be the anticipation of good to be done. ,Jt is not thus that public instructors have gene rally proceeded. They have erected for them selves, in the field of moral action, a high throne; thence, in the character of absolute and infallible monarchs, have they dictated to the world below, and sent out their commands and prohibitions for prompt and peremptory recognition. The wantonness of a political ruler has often been the topic of animadversion ; the self-erected arbitrator wielding like the madman in his cell his imaginary sceptre, is, in truth, more egre- giously wanton. A certain sense of responsi bility — a fear of reaction may control the despotism of an acknowledged tyrant, but where DEONTOLOGY EXPLAINED. 31 is the control which is to check the waywardness and presumption of the self-elected dictator of moralsT/ LHis-lone is the tone of the pedagogue or the magistrate ; he is strong and wise, and knowing and virtuous. His readers are weak, and foolish, and ignorant, ' and vicious ; — his voice is the voice of power, — and it is from the superiority of his wisdom that his power is derived.; And if all this were so without prejudice to to the public, it might be the gratification of pride to the individual — pleasure to him — and so much pleasure gained. But the misfortune t • - is, that the assumption of this authority has for its natural attendants — indolence and igno rance. I Even where precepts are founded on good reasons, the development of those reasons is a matter of considerable exertion and diffi culty — it is a task to which few have been found competent. But to set up laws and precepts is a task of no difficulty at all — a task to which all men are competent, the foolish as well as the wise, — a task wLich the foolish indeed are most eager to engage in, — for ignorance has no more convenient cloak than arrogance. The talisman of arrogance, indolence, and ignorance, is to be found in a single word, an authoritative imposture, which in these pages it will be frequently necessary to unveil. It is 32 DEONTOLOGV. the word 'ought' — 'ought or ought not,' as circumstances may be. ' In,deciding ' You ought to do this — you ought not to do it/— is not every question of morals set at resjtj[ / If the use of the word be admissible at all, it ' ought ' to be banished from the vocabulary of morals. There is another word, which has a talismanic virtue too, and which might be wielded to de stroy many fatal and fallacious positions. ' You ought y — 'you ought not/ says the dogmatist. Why ? retorts the inquirer — Why ? To say ' you ought/ is easy in the extreme. To stand the searching penetration of a Why? is not so easy. Why ought I ? Because you ought — is the not unfrequent reply ; — on which the Why ? comes back again with the added advantage of having obtained a victory. It cannot, may it be answered, be the mere love of ease that drives the instructor to adopt this phraseology; the love of ease would not induce him to write even thus glibly and un wisely, but would keep him from writing at all. But motives there are stronger than the love of ease. There may be advantages of many sorts growing out of a particular line of argu ment. _Oiit of conformity with public opinion grows reputation— out of reputation, wealth and DEONTOLOGY EXPLAINED. 33 power. A man must keep well with public opinion. To oppose current prejudices, to bend back an established bias, can hardly be the conduct of him who desires to present him self in fair proportions to the worldly The world's judgment is on the side of seve rity ; for (in the restraints imposed upon his neighbour, every man feels an increase of his own power — a gratification of his own pride. He easily prepares for himself an exemption that shall satisfy his own mind, while, by indulging in the strong language of animadversion, he gives evidence that he is free from the offence which he so vehemently reprobates — for who would be forward in passing condemnation on himself?/ From laxity he has nothing to hope — everything to fear ; from severity everything to hope, and nothing to fear— j-aiic^so^ with ' ought' and ' ought not' for his instruments, he goes on laying commands and prohibitions upon his fellows — imposing chains and burthens — not the less galling and afflictive because they have their source in metaphors and fictions. J In all this there is seemingly much profit, and little pain. Little waste of toil — little waste of thought. Observation, inquiry, reflection — these are all superfluous, as superfluous as they are la borious. IFolly and arrogance — the blindest folly and the most assuming arrogance — find them- VOL. I. D 34 DEONTOLOGY. selves altogether at their ease. By these caterers to the moral tastej pleasures are ordered off the table — pains ordered on instead of theny, just as by the word of the physician of Barataria, the meat was marched away from the presence of the famished Sancho ; but the physician of Barataria did not replace it by poison. Sacrifice' — sacrifice is the demand of the every day moralist^ Sacrifice, taken by itself, is mis chievous, and mischievous is the influence that connects morality with suffering. Little does he seem to be aware how far morality may be effective without any thing painful. Its associa tions are cheerfulness and joy — not gloom and misery. Certain it is, the less the sacrifice made of happiness, the more must there be of happiness remaining. Let it be obtained gratis where it can — where it cannot be had without sacrifice, let the sacrifice be as small as possible; where the sacrifice must be great, let it be ascer tained that the happiness will be greater. This is the true economy of pleasure — this is the pro lific cultivation of virtue. PZDXTOLOGY, or that which is proper, has been chosen as a fitter term than any other which could be found, to represent in the field of mo rals, the principle of Utilitarianism , or that which is useful. Utilitarianism offers too vague and undefined an impression to the mind. If the DEONTOLOGY EXPLAINED. 35 term could be immediately and directly associ ated with the production of felicity, it might be appropriately and conveniently employed. The occasions on which the deontological principle is called into action, are either perma nent or transient — public or private. Public occasions are those which exist between man and man, as members of society in general — a large proportion of which occasions, which may be properly called political, do not come within the scope of this work. " Man's private relations .are either natural or factitious — those which may be considered as having birth for their source, and those which are accidental. These divisions will be found convenient on the demamj for the practical application of the moral code.] The word utility, with its conjugates, use ful and useless, uselessness and usefulness, has not been found applicable to all the cases where the principle itself is brought into operation. In some instances it appears too weak to ex press the force of the obligation of which it is desirable to give the idea. The mind will not be satisfied with such phrases as, 'It is useless to commit murder' — or, ' it would be useful to pre vent it :' and so of incendiarism and acts of great magnitude of mischief. Hence its insufficiency in the field of legislation. The principles of asceticism and sentimental- 36 DEONTOLOGY. ism being in a state of rivalry with the principle of utility, the employment of the term might be made, on every occasion, the ground for reject ing propositions which otherwise would be admitted. It pre-supposes, as it were, the truth of the doctrine of utility. In the word propriety, with its conjugates, proper and improper, the desideratum appears to have been found. It is a natural emanation from Deontology, or the knowledge of what is proper. There is no objection to it in respect of inten sity of import: no crime, however heinous, but will be admitted to be improper. It is true, that to the rhetorician, an expression thus used may appear unsuited to the occasion, and he may deem the word itself improper. His object being to put others in a passion, his course is to appear to be in a passion himself; while, by so unexciting a term, not passion, but the absence of passion is expressed. But to the logician such an objection will not be formidable ; and it is for logical, and not for rhetorical purposes, that the word is wanted. It has, too, the usefulness of impartiality. It does not of itself decide between any of the systems — and may be applied with equal pro priety to the developement of each. Probably neither the ascetic nor the sentimentalist will DEONTOLOGY EXPLAINED. 37 regard it as inappropriate, unless on the ground of its coolness. Both will certainly admit to be proper that of which they approve ; both that of which they disapprove, to be improper. It will, at all events, serve to express the two characters of an act, leaving any additional lan guage of praise or blame to be applied at will. It is the announcement of a judgment formed, and that without any intimation of the affections with which that judgment has been accompa nied, or the ground on which it has been deter mined. To the Utilitarian it will have the convenience of covering the whole domain of action, and giving expression to the sentiment of Approba tion or disapprobation, to whichever part of the field of duty the act may belong. 38 DEONTOLOGY. CHAPTER III. ANTI-DEONTOLOGICAL PROPOSITIONS REMOVED SUMMUM BONUM. BEFORE the edifice of moral truth can be erected it is needful to clear away a vast heap of rubbish which obstructs the progress of the moral architect^/ Motives different from those which utility recognises — ends hostile to those which utility proposes, have been and are the topics of self-elected moralists. When these are disposed of, the path of the Deontologist will be clear ; until they are disposed of, his path will be perplexed with their intrusions. 'The end of the Deontologist — it cannot be too often repeated — is happiness. ' Something that is not happiness, something different, something contradistinguished from happiness, was proposed by ancient philosophers. It was the summum bonum. And the summum bonum, the sovereign good, we can hardly better trace than in that accre dited history of it, to be found in the Oxford Compendium, once the text-book and authority of that famous university. SUMMUM BONUM. 39 In what does the summum bonum consist? The question was debated by multitudes, de bated from generation to generation, by men assuming to themselves the dictatorship of right and wrong. The summum bonum, in what does it consist ? What does the term signify ? Nonsense, and nothing more. The summum bonum, — the sovereign good — what is it ? The philosopher's stone that con verts all metals into gold — the balm Hygeian that cures all manner of diseases. It is this thing, and that thing, and the other thing — it is any thing but pleasure — it is the Irishman's apple-pie made of nothing but quinces. If it were any thing, what would it be? Could it be anything but pleasure ? A pleasure, or the cause of pleasure? Supreme pleasure — pleasure without pain — happiness maximised ? What fool has there ever been so foolish as not to know that by no man, in no time, at no place, has such a prize been ever found ? In every walk of discipline error is a sort of vestibule through which men are condemned to pass on their approaches towards truth. ^Wliile Xenophon was writing history, and Eu clid giving instruction in geometry, Socrates and Plato were talking nonsense under pretence of teaching wisdom and morality. /This morality of 40 DEONTOLOGY. theirs consisted in words, — this wisdom of theirs was the denial of matters known to every man's experience, and the assertion of other matters opposed to every man's experience. And ex actly in the proportion in which their notions on this subject differed from those of the mass of mankind, exactly in that proportion were they below the level of mankind. The people who took no pleasure in the uttering of any such nonsense ; the people were contented to reap common pleasures under the guidance of common sense. They were called ignorant and the vulgar herd, yet they crowded into their existence a balance of well-being, and most of them now and then a portion of happiness. Well-being their ordinary fare, happiness, a slight taste of it for an occasional feast. This was good enough for the ignorant vulgar; not so for the learned sages, — men, who by whatever name they called their own sageships, were called by others wisest of men , wise men ( or half virtue, is awarded. These half-virtues are called by the author of the Oxford Compendium, * only rudiments/ and evidence of * good dispositions3 towards ' a habit of virtue;' but ' entire virtues/ he says, they are by no means to be denominated.* He will, however, have them subject to * me diocrity' or moderation (rnediocritas^) as the dominant virtue, after all. According to him, virtue consists in doing, without the cost of any sacrifice, what is right • Compendium, p. 69. f The allusion here is to another Aristotelian tenet, that, in every case, virtue consists — that every species of virtue consists — in mediocrity. 148 DEONTOLOGY. to be done, and for every whole virtue there is a half-virtue. And, with a limitation, for which it is not very easy to discover the reason, the half-virtues are paired off with the whole virtues. The half-virtues, he avows, have as many classes as the whole ones, but they must be grouped under certain genera. And so he goes on to arrange his half-virtues under two heads — continentia et tolerantia, con tinence and tolerance, — corresponding, he says, with the concupiscent and irascible appetites ; continence being taken in hand by concupis cence, and tolerance by irascibility. Now the difference between the whole and the half vir tues being constituted only by the presence or absence of reluctance, there seems no reason why the same division should not apply to every part of the field of virtue. But the farther he proceeds the deeper is the darkness gathered round him, and the imperfection of his classifi cation becomes palpable. Does he mean by tolerantia, the subjection of one's self to bodily pain? Truly does he, if he is to be believed. In fact he says so, in so many words.* But this tolerance, he continues, is a virtus imperfecta (an imperfect virtue) whose value * Page 70. VIRTUE DEFINED. 149 certainly he hesitates to put too prominently forward, and whose influence, he fears, may be interfered with through imbecility of mind.* Tolerance, by which he means the power of suffering — and not the virtue of candid and benevolent judgment — will, after all, be found to have been too much honored by the Oxonian's eulogy. It is not a half-virtue. It is no virtue at all. It is the physical disposition to resist the influences of pain, which nature has given to some men and denied to others, without adding to or subtracting from the virtues of those who have it, or those who have it not. The irascible appetite is that which seeks to visit with its ill-will the object of its anger — the appetite seeking its gratification by the pro duction of pain in the breast of him who is the subject of its visitation. But the seat of the pain produced by anger is really the heart of the angry person. Does this make him virtuous, which it ought to do, according to the Aristote lian definition ? Yet, according to the view of the Oxford teacher of morality, this subject, which he has left involved in such midnight obscurity, is im portant in the very highest degree. On it de pends the dreadful difference between salvation and damnation. Yet these very qualities — this * Page 71. 150 DEONTOLOGY. continence and tolerance, which Aristotle dis misses with the light character of imperfect virtues — are, in a theological point of view (so says the Oxonian moralist), not only among the most perfect, but among the most arduous virtues. According to Aristotle's morality, half is no more than half; a half- virtue is but a half-virtue. According to Oxford theology, half is equal to, if not greater than the whole. But in this, mystery is made out of every thing, and out of nothing ; and the more mystery the more merit. It would, indeed, have been well, if to the Aristotelian appetites, the appetite for mystery had been added by the Oxonian ; an appetite which may be described as being always in the forest of so-called religion, hunting for absur dity and nonsense, and feeding upon its aliment with a relish directly proportioned to its gross- ness. Before the title of virtue is demanded for an action, its conduciveness to happiness must be proved. According to Aristotle and his Oxford disciple, virtue consists in mediocrity — so in Latin, at least ;> for it may be thought that moderation is the more fit translation of media- critas ; but, at all events, it is mediocritas. And here let it be remarked, by the way, that if morality had been intended for use — if it had been thought good enough for the business of VIRTUE MWNED. 151 life, a living language, and not a dead one, would have been employed for teaching it : the language of the many, not the language of the few. Now what is the value of a definition? That we may know the thing defined. Of a description? Clearly that we may recognize the thing described. And let us see whether the end is accomplished here. The virtue is named, it is stuck between two qualities of the same character, which are not virtues ; in one of which the qualities of the virtues are deficient, in the other they are ex cessive: here is your designation of virtue, here is the example, running through the whole string of virtues. The only thing, then, need ful, is to show what, on each occasion, is the exact quantity of the quality out of which virtue is made, to produce it ready for use, correctly weighed out, neither too much nor too little ; for if you get it not in the exact quantity, get what you may, you will not get virtue. But for this all-important object you will find no help from our moralist. There are, he tells you, three doses of the moral medicine: there is the proper dose, the excessive dose, and the deficient dose. In the proper dose there is health and safety ; in the others peril and perdition. Has he not noted down the sanatory quantity? Not he! Are there no 152 DEONTOLOGY. figures, no means of estimate in his prescription? Nothing like them. If a physician treat of diseases, he does not satisfy himself with scribbling down their names, but thinks it useful, finds it necessary, indeed, to record their symptoms. Not so our moralist. His virtues are names, without symptoms : he talks of virtue ; but how virtue is to be sepa rated from that which is not virtue, forms no portion of his care. Even common phraseology, the accustomed use of the terms of right and wrong, justice and injustice, have, in their habitual employ* ment, a more decided bearing upon the welfare of society than is given to the virtues by the ethical Oxonian. All men have a sort of notion that government and legislation, and religion and morality, have, or ought to have, a bene ficial influence upon the public happiness. On what other ground, indeed, can they be recom mended? But on that ground the Oxford moralist makes no stand. But the Oxford Compendium offers a series of definitions for virtue, out of which a man may take which he pleases. 1 . ' Virtue is an elective habit, consisting in mediocrity (or in a medium) in regard to our selves, and as a prudent man would prescribe it.' Let who can make sense of this. If it have VIRTUE DEFINED. 153 any meaning^ the meaning is, that there are two virtues, mediocrity and prudence, and that these two are one. 2. ' Virtue consists in the conformity of our actions to the divine will.' Good. But the difficulty is to know the divine will on every occasion. The phraseology of the Bible is general, not particular ; some times, too, the meaning may be doubtful, and subject to dispute. And what is the divine will, as taught in the Bible? What is it, what can it be but to produce happiness ? What other motive, what other end has it proposed to obedience ? The divine will is benignant, bene volent, beneficent. What do these terms imply but happiness-intending, happiness-producing ? So that, if the Oxford moralist has any mean ing—if the words are not used for the mere purposes of delusion — his meaning must be our meaning. And, in that case, he might have avoided all ambiguity of expression. 3. * Virtue consists in the conformity of our actions to right reason/ Right reason ? That very reason which the authorities of Oxford so often declare to be at variance with the divine will. Human reason, that is the standard, is it not? Whose right reason ? Mine, or the man's who differs from me? Mine, of course; for I cannot hold any 154 DEONTOLOGY. man's reason to be right which I hold to be wrong. And I hold his to be wrong, because I differ from him. Mine, or the Oxford man's ? Mine. The question is settled. And now let me dogmatize like the rfest. 4. ' Virtue consists' — the divine will and right reason consist— ' in mediocrity,' Here, at last, we have a standard by which to measure the divine will and right reason too, and virtue, as the child of both. And now, reader, all doubts and difficulties being removed, your moral principle is put into your hand, that with it you may work your wonders. So says Aristotle, so says Oxford. But what says utility ? What are the really valuable virtues, what the subservient virtues which grow out of them ? Taking for the standard and the test of virtue its conducive- ness to well-being, it is believed, as has been said above, that all the modifications of virtue may be arranged under the two heads of pru dence and beneficence. Beyond these there is no intrinsically valuable virtue. To one or other of these every useful moral quality will be found to belong. These, then, may be called the primary virtues. Take away prudence, take away benevolence, from the tree of morals, you strip it of all its flowers and fruits, of its strength, its beauty, and its use. You have a VIRTUE DEFINED. 155 worthless, unproductive trunk, smitten with barrenness, the mere cumberer of the ground. The value of the whole tribe of ancillary or secondary virtues depends altogether on their subserviency to these two primary virtues. Hence it follows — 1. That if the primary virtues were not useful, neither could the secondary virtues be so. 2. That their utility must con sist in advancing the same ends which it is the object of the primary virtues to advance. 3. The tendency of the primary virtues is inva riably towards usefulness, in the case of some person or other on whom they are exercised, whether useful or not to human society on the whole. 4. The usefulness of the secondary virtues is to be measured by their tendency to produce those effects which it is the tendency of the primary virtues to produce. 5. Their usefulness must be measured by the degree in which they contribute to advance those ends, which are the ends of the primary virtues. Occasion will be found to bring the whole of the secondary virtues under review, and to test their value by the principles which have been here developed. The modes in which the various virtues may be brought into operation — by discourse, by writing, or by deportment — belong to the prac tical branch of the subject. 156 DEONTOLOGY. CHAPTER XL SELF-INTEREST, OR SELF-REGARDING PRUDENCE. NATURE, artless and untutored nature, engages man in the pursuit of immediate pleasure, and in the avoidance of immediate pain. What reason can effect is to prevent the sacrifice of a greater distant pleasure, or the visitation of a greater distant pain in exchange for those which are present ; in other words, to prevent a miscalculation in the amount of happiness. In this, too, consists the whole of virtue, which ;is but the sacrifice of a smaller present satis faction, in the shape of a temptation, to a satis faction of greater magnitude, but more remote, which is, in fact, a recompense. What can be done for morality, in the field of self-interest, is to show how much a man's own happiness depends upon himself, how much on the effects his conduct produces in the breasts of those with whom he is connected by the ties of mutual sympathy; how much the interest which others feel in his happiness, and how much the desire to promote it depend on his own doings. Suppose a man wedded to intoxication. He SELF-REGARDING PRUDENCE. 157 will be taught to consider and weigh the amount of pleasure and pain growing out of his conduct. He will view, on one side, the intensity and the duration of the pleasurable excitement. This will be the account on the side of profit. Per contra, he will be led to estimate — • 1. Sickness and other effects prejudicial to health, 2. Future contingent pains, growing out of probable debility and disease. 3. The loss of time and the loss of money, and these in proportion to the value of time and money in his individual case. 4. The pain produced in the minds of those who are dear to him ; as, for instance, a parent, a wife, a child. 5. The disrepute attached to the practice ; the loss of reputation in the eyes of others. 6. The risk of legal punishment, and the disgrace attaching to it ; as when the public exhibition of that temporary insanity, produced by intoxi cation, is visited by the laws. 7. The risk of punishments attached to crimes which a man is liable to commit while gratifying the pro pensity to inebriety. 8. The misery produced by apprehension of punishment in a future state of being. All these will probably lead him to discover that he purchases the pleasures of intoxication at too great a cost. He will see that morality, which is virtue, arid happiness, which is self- 158 DEONTOLOGY. interest, counsel him to avoid excess. He has the same motive to subdue his intemperate propensities that a man has, who, in the pur suit of wealth, can choose between gaining much and gaining little. Deontology asks no ultimate sacrifice; her lessons propose a balance of enjoyment to the man with whom she rea sons. He is in search of pleasure ; she encou rages him in the search, she allows it to be wise, honorable, and virtuous ; but she entreats him not to err by an erroneous arithmetic ; she represents a futurity, a probably adjacent futu rity, with its pleasures and pains. She asks whether the enjoyment which is taken to-day will not have to be repaid to-morrow, or the clay after, with usurious and intolerable interest. She implores that the same prudent calculation which every wise man applies to his daily concerns, may be applied to the most impor tant of all concerns, those of felicity and misery. Deontology professes no scorn for that very selfishness to which vice itself appeals. She surrenders every point which cannot be proved to be beneficial to the individual. She consents even to set aside the code of the lawgiver and the dogmas of the divine. She takes for granted that these cannot be unfriendly to her influences, that neither legislation nor religion are hostile to morality ; and she insists that morality shall SELF-REGARDING PRUDENCE. 159 not be opposed to happiness. Make out to her a case against human felicity, and she. is smit ten with silence and with helplessness. She acknowledges that even the drunkard is pro posing to himself a proper end ; but she is able to show him that his end will not be accom plished by drunkenness. She assumes nothing but that which no man will deny — namely, that all men wish to be happy. She has no purpose to answer by despotic dogmatizing. Her mission is to invite to a sober reckoning of good and evil. She has no interest in this or that course of action, in one result or another, but in so far as there is to be something of happiness abstracted from the whole. All that she proposes is to put a bridle upon precipi tancy, to prevent rashness from taking irre vocable steps, and entering upon foolish bar gains. She has no quarrel with any species of pleasure which does not associate itself with a more than counterbalancing portion of pain. In a word, she ministers to selfishness, and, like a wise and active steward, makes the most of every man's rent-roll of felicity. But she is not blind nor thoughtless. She knows that the present will soon be the past, and that the opinions of this hour will be modi fied by the experience of the next. Hence she desires that the important element of that which 160 DEONTOLOGY. v .it to be may not be left out of the calculation of that which is. The teaching is — Weigh every thing, weigh every thing well that belongs to the bargain. Make the most of what is given you to enjoy now ; but if suffering is behind, if enjoyments greater than those you are grasp ing are to be surrendered, as the payment for them, where is your prudence ? If, for the purchase of the enjoyment you cevet, you inflict pain upon others greater than your enjoyment, where is your benevolence ? And if, from the infliction of that pain upon others, they retaliate on you with interest, or abstract from your enjoyments a greater sum than that of which you deprived them, where, again, is your pru dence ? In fact, the self-esteem which takes not into account any thing future, has as little in it of prudence as of benevolence. It is truly the killing the goose for the golden egg.\ * Myself/ ' myself/ is but the cry of insensibility to happiness or unhappiness from external sources; and insensibility to the pressure of evil is a clear advantage to its possessor, provided, that insensibility brings with it no re-action from others. Phocion's self-esteem lessened his sense of his own misfortune. There was no benevolence, no courtesy in his representing himself as an SELF-REGARDING PRUDENCE, 101 object of greater admiration to his fellow-sufferer than his fellow-sufferer was to himself. This was mere arrogance. Vitellius's self-esteem led him to demand respect, because he had possessed the highest portion of prosperity. If that consoled him, so much the better for him, and nothing the worse for others. But self-regarding prudence is not only a virtue — it is a virtue on which the very exist ence of the race depends. If I thought more about you than I thought about myself, I should be the blind leading the blind, and we should fall into the ditch together. It is as impossible that your pleasures should be better to me than my own, as that your eye-sight should be better to me than my own. My happiness and my unhappiness are as much a part of me as any of my faculties or organs, and I might as well profess to feel your tooth-ache more keenly than you do, as to be more interested in your well-being than in rny own well-being. There are, however, many who so exaggerate the selfish principle as to think that, by swel ling their notions of themselves, they are still serving their race. But how? Does a man's pride or vanity make others happier? If so, there is double gain. We have got hold of a pleasure, and so VOL. i. M 1G2 DEONTOLOGY. have others. Does it not affect others, either for better or worse ? Still there is a gain, for man has a pleasure in his own glorification. Does his pride or his vanity bring annoyance to the bosoms of others ? There is something thrown into the other scale ; the calculation must be made ; all the annoyances suffered by all those who are annoyed, must be added together, and weighed against the pleasures of the man's pride or vanity. It will be, perhaps, found that the annoyances caused to others are pro portioned to the intensity of his own self-gra tification. It is clear that, in such a case, the balance will be increased in proportion. The sun of Deontology irradiates the adjacent regions of prudence and benevolence. By it light is substituted to darkness, order to chaos. It solves all intricate problems, and all perplex ing difficulties vanish before it. By it alone can be traced out the affinities, — from it alone can be deduced the relations between the seve ral classes of moral qualities ; through it alone can the limits between virtue and vice be disco vered. All anomalies may be reduced by it, and by it alone, to harmony and regularity. By it, and by it alone, a variety of distinctions, which have stood in an unintelligible or insulated shape, may be brought into connection or contrast. It is the spear of Ithuriel, by which evil and SELF-REGARDING PRUDENCE. 163 good may be detected, and made to present themselves in their own true characters. There has been among moralists a vehement disposition to shut out the influence of the self- regarding principle from the mind. Why this reluctance to admit, as a motive, that which is and must be the strongest of all motives — a man's regard for himself? Why is not self-love to be brought into the field ? It is from a sort of bashfulness — a disposition to consider that principle to which all the actions and passions of men owe their birth, as the partie honteuse of our nature. But with the recognition of the principle, that an enlightened regard to self-interest is the best guarantee for good conduct, the knowledge and the practice of morality have undoubtedly made considerable progress, and delightful it is to trace the slow but visible march of virtue. It will lose nothing of its stability, nothing of its power, when it is discovered to be founded on interest. That interest some men will not see, and others will turn away with scorn from the contemplation of it. Declaimers would ask whether, in an age like this, which they call degenerate,. a. man would sacrifice his life for the benefit of his country. Yes ! There is many and many a man, who, upon 164 DEONTOLOGY. such calls as have formerly met with the like obedience, would, for his country, surrender his existence with pleasure. Does it follow that, in this or in any thing else, he would act without an interest ? No such thing. Nothing like it : it is not in man's nature. And precisely the same argument holds good in man's aberrations from duty. They are the miscalculations of interest. ' There is no man doth a wrong for the wrong's sake ; but thereby to purchase himself profit or pleasure.' This grand truism was not hidden from Lord Bacon. His was a mind to be struck with the beauty of truth wherever it met him ; but his was not an age when- to pursue it to the utmost was either practicable or safe. Yet he could not fail to draw the deduction, that if vices were upon the whole account pro fitable, the virtuous man would be the sinner. The sacrifice of interests presents itself ab stractedly, as something grand and virtuous, because it is taken for granted that the plea sure one man flings away must necessarily be gathered up by another. And supposing no pleasure were lost in the transfer, and no plea sure gained, it is clear that the whole sum of happiness would continue just as it was, notwithstanding a million shiftings from one possessor to another. But in the commerce of SELF-REGARDING PRUDENCE. 165 happiness, as in that of wealth, the prominent question is, how to make circulation assist pro duction. Hence, it is no more fit to call disin terestedness a virtue in moral economy, than to call expenditure a merit in political economy. Disinterestedness may exist among the rash and the reckless; but a man disinterested on reflection is happily seldom to be found. Show me the man who throws away more of the elements of felicity than he creates, and I will show you a fool and a prodigal. Show me the man who deprives himself of more good than he communicates to another, and I will show you a man ignorant of the elementary arithmetic of morality. Out of self-regarding prudence, as a primary virtue, grow temperance and continence, as secondary virtues. The breach of them brings the actor into the regions of pain ; the habitual breach of them leaves a result of unhappiness, upon which the eye of prudence cannot turn without discerning the balance of suffering that is left behind. 166 DEONTOLOGY. CHAPTER XII. PRUDENCE AS RESPECTS OTHERS, OR EXTRA- REGARDING PRUDENCE. THOUGH it belongs to Government to give increase and extension to the connection which exists between prudence and effective benevo lence wherever the political sanction will apply, it is the duty of the public teacher of morality to point out their accordance, and to give to that accordance all the action and effect of which it is susceptible through his influence. It is to public opinion, or in other words, to the popular or moral sanction, that we must mainly look for the action of the social on the self-regarding feelings. Of the tribunal of public opinion every individual of the community may be a member; every one who gives to his estimate of the conduct of others any expression by words or deeds is an acting member, and every man who takes upon himself to write is a leading member ; his influence will be propor tioned to the approbation he receives from his readers, and the strength of the impression he conveys to their minds ; and again, on the EXTRA-REGARDING PRUDENCE. 167 number and influence of such readers. To their concurrence and co-operation he must turn for the measures of his own success. A man is prompted by ill-will to aim a blow at another. His ill-will may be restrained by the apprehension that the blow will be returned by the person at whom it is aimed, or by a third party who is a looker-on ; or, secondly, he may be restrained by the apprehension of legal punish ment. In one case the physical, in the other the political sanction is operative ; and there is in neither any demand for the application of the Deontological principle. But where these fail, where they provide no adequate remedy, come the popular and the social sanctions, to fill up that portion of the field of action which is unoccupied by other motives. These two sanctions are intimately and closely allied, for the social relations stretch naturally and neces sarily into the whole frame of society. By some social link, more or less efficient, almost every man is bound to the great body of the public. The circle widens, the intimacy strengthens as society becomes more and more intelligent. The interest^m a family ex tends to a tribe, from a tribe to a province, from a province to a nation, from a nation to mankind. And as political and Deontological science become better understood, the depend- 168 DEONTOLOGY, ence of every man upon the good opinion of all besides will be increased, and the moral sanction grow stronger and stronger. Its strength too will be greatly heightened by a more correct appreciation of its own power, so that a period may be anticipated in which the public mind will not err in its estimate of duty, and when the moral will supersede a portion of the political sanction. But to be a little more particular. The influ ence of an act upon others whose happiness is affected by it, may be fitly considered with reference to the particular case. It is assumed, that a man by a blow inflicts corporal injury upon another. He who gives the blow has, in the first place, to apprehend retaliation in the shape of the same or similar personal injury. This apprehension is the physical sanction. The political or legal sanction, the risk of the inter ference of the magistrate, may, and probably will apply here, though that interference can in fact be safely grounded on no other principle than that on which Deontology itself rests, namely, the greatest happiness principle. But whether or not the political or the physical sanction are called into exertion, the moral sanction will, at all events, be put into operation. For, as experience and observation have taught that such deeds of violence are the sources of EXTRA-REGARDING PRUDENCE. 169 suffering, disapprobation will have place, de pending for its amount on the degree of suffering inflicted. Nor can the sympathetic and social sanction be without its effect; for though in the rude states of society that sanction may be so weak as to produce no restraint, and though in every state of society it is susceptible of great variation, as between individual and individual, jn a period of civilization like that to which threse thoughts are addressed, the social sanction becomes highly operative, and it will be operative in cases where the more general moral sanction may sometimes fail of its effect. He who would show indifference to the happiness of those with whom he is wholly unconnected, might be less disposed to show indifference to that of his friends or family, on whom he more immediately depends for his own happiness. As far as it exists, though spread over a nar rower field, the sympathetic sanction must be stronger than the moral. For as few persons can contemplate altogether without uneasiness the sufferings of a fellow creature, especially if presented in a particular manner to their perception or imagination, still less can they witness with indifference those of a friend. The sense of sympathy is universal. Perhaps there never existed a human being who had reached full age without the experience of 170 DEONTOLOGY. pleasure at another's pleasure, of uneasiness at at another's pain. It may be narrowed to a domestic circle, and that circle may be as it were at war with mankind. Community of interest, similarity of opinion, are sources whence it springs. This sympathy then will operate as a restraint against the giving pain. It will always operate except where some stronger counter- motive acts in a contrary direction. And all these sanctions act with accumulating power ; for as the mind of individual man, if looked at from generation to generation, will be found increasing in strength and steadiness, in the knowledge of, and the command over its several faculties, and in the amount of observation and experience which it accumulates for its own use and guidance, so it may reasonably be ex pected, that the several sanctions which are associated with the universal mind will obtain more and more of their fit developement ; and so with the species. There is a period in which the self-regarding principle is the only one in very active operation ; it occupies the whole sphere of mind, scarcely going beyond the mere physical sanction ; so that conduct is little more than a grasping at immediate enjoyment, with out any calculation of remote happiness or un- happiness. This is the mere sensual state, in close association with which come the irascible EXTRA-REGARDING PRUDENCE. 171 or dissocial affections (as they are called by Aristotle), which, though so distinct in character, operate towards the same end. The sensual affec tions are checked by the operation of the iras cible excited in those among whom the sensual seek their gratification; by the fear of retaliation and retribution as the natural consequences of resentment. It has been remarked that, as in the individual, so in society at large the affection of sympathy is in its weakest state during the earliest period of existence. As age and ex perience advance it receives additional force and efficiency. It extends its influence for the most part with the extension of existence, beginning with the small immediate relations where the ties of consanguinity, affinity, domes tic contract, or friendly intercourse, are strongest, and advancing with experience and mental culture into a widening field of action. Its links become multifarious, and capable of great extension and increase. They spread into divers circles, domestic, social, professional, civic, provincial, national, ultra-national, univer sal ; some independant of and others connected with each other. And in so much and so far as the sympathetic affections can be called into action, their tendencies must be to increase the happiness of him who exercises them ; while if these happiness-producing tendencies lead to 172 DEONTOLOGY. no consequences of a contrary effect, or to no consequences of equal amount, the result is a clear accession to the general stock of happiness. And thus even the self-regarding affection, employed as a source of selfish enjoyment, ^brings into action a great mass of public hap piness. The very contagion of the self-regard ing principle is beneficent. A man witnessing the services rendered by his neighbour, to his neighbour's neighbour, contracts and catches, as it were, a propensity to requite the friend liness with his own friendliness, to bestow upon the author of benefits, benefits like those he has bestowed. The cheapest mode of requital, and considering its extreme facility not the least efficacious, is on all occasions to give to to the benevolent affections an outward ex pression, to bring into conversation as frequently as practicable the language of goodwill. To praise the virtuous doings of another man is to dispense a positive recompense to virtue, and at the same time to direct the popular sanction to the encouragement of similar acts, and thus does the principle of self produce the social affection, and the social in its turn the popular; and all combine together to increase the general good. But the sympathies excited in favor of an individual, are they dependent on the influence EXTRA-REGARDING PRUDENCE. 173 of his actions upon the general good ? Is a man judged of by the conduciveness of his conduct to the public happiness ? Alas, not always, for sympathy to a great extent, approbation to a vast amount, have frequently been excited, not by acts productive of good, but by acts produc tive of evil ; not by conduct favourable to human happiness, but detrimental and destructive to happiness in the highest degree: — by victory and conquest for example, by depredation, devastation and slaughter on the widest scale, or by the acquisition or possession of power ; power in unbounded quantity, however obtained, however exercised. And even with respect to acts whose conse quences have been in some respects beneficial to the community, it may have happened that the benefit was neither pure nor preponderant. Now as the tendency of sympathy is always to produce a repetition of the act which it approves, the moral sanction may be misdirected to the creation of acts pernicious on the whole to the well-being of society. An act which in its earliest and most obvious effects is beneficial, may, when the whole of its effects are seen together, and calmly calculated, be upon the balance pernicious. So an act, whose instant and apparent consequence is pernicious, may upon the balance be beneficial, In both cases 174 DEONTOLOGY. it is clear that the sympathy which should lead to the production of the one act, and the antipathy which would prevent the production of the other, would be alike injurious to the public happiness, and thence at variance with the sound principles of morality. To detect the fallacies which lie hid under the surface, to prevent the aberrations of sympathy and anti pathy, to bring to view and to call into activity those springs of action whose operation leads to an undoubted balance of happiness, is the important part of moral science. The Deontologist, it must always be remem bered, has no coercive power, and it may perhaps be somewhat too hastily inferred that all his occupation will end in the putting together a number of sentences, inoperative in their influ ence on human conduct. But it is presumed that three favorable consequence, at least, may result from his labors. Where he cannot create a motive he may point out its existence. He may bring to view, and show the bearing upon human felicity, of those springs of action which form a part of every man's mind, however hidden from observation, or inert in operation. He may point out consequences of action and forbear ance which had not presented themselves to the actor. EXTRA-REGARDING PRUDENCE. 175 Again, he may give more efficiency to the popular moral sanction; he may proclaim its ordinances ; and if he is unable to do this, he may take upon himself the initiative of its laws, and propose for public consideration appropriate topics to aid its recognition. Motions, at least, in favor of the public weal may emanate from him with the chance of approving themselves to the minds of those to whom they are addressed. And lastly, he may influence those in whose hands are the powers of legislation, or the executive powers of the state, to give to the popular sanction the stronger influence of the political, wherever it is applicable to the pro duction of that end, which cannot be too often brought to view — the maximization of the public happiness. Intimately connected with the dictates of prudence are those of beneficence. To a great extent, the prudential considerations prescribe benevolent action. The self-regarding calcula- / tion cannot leave out of view the happiness of ^ others. 176 DEONTOLOGY. CHAPTER XIII. EFFECTIVE BENEVOLENCE, EFFECTIVE benevolence has been already intro duced to notice, as consisting of two branches, \/ the positive, or pleasure-conferring branch ; the . negative, or that which abstains from pain- giving to others. The word benevolence im plies the disposition to do the acts of bene ficence. The field of benevolence, therefore, is co-extensive with that of beneficence ; not that either of them has necessarily the other for its companion ; there may be benevolence, with out the power of bringing its impulses into action, and there may be beneficence, without the slightest portion of good-will. The good produced by effective benevolence is small in proportion to that produced by the personal motives. The sympathetic affections are not, cannot be, as strong as the self-regard ing affections. The wealth transferred, the means of subsistence circulated, the abundance produced for the sake of others, are trifling, when weighed against the amount of that which is • set in motion for our own sakes. That which EFFECTIVE BENEVOLENCE — NEGATIVE. 177 0 is given without equivalent is little indeed as contrasted with that which is paid for or bar tered in the way of commerce. The voluntary contributions to government, for the public benefit, bear a small proportion to the sums which are levied by compulsory requisitions. In the eye of the sentimentalist, benevolence, whether followed or not by beneficence, is apt to engross the greatest portion of his favor, and his efforts are directed to obtain for it the greatest portion of public applause. But bene volence is a useless tree, unless it bears the fruits of beneficence; and feelings, by whatever names they are called, are wholly valueless, unless in so far as they are the prompters of beneficent actions. Benevolence standing alone is but the shadow of virtue ; it is only when it becomes efficient that it partakes of the sub stance of virtue. To a great extent, it must be added, the dictates of prudence prescribe the laws of effec tive benevolence, and occupy, in mutual har mony, the same part of the field of duty. A man who injures himself more than he benefits others by no means serves the cause of virtue, for he diminishes the amount of happiness. Benevolence, or sympathy, may be a cause of fruitless pain, where it cannot exert itself in acts of beneficence. It is no part of the re- VOL. i. N 178 DEONTOLOGY. quirements of virtue that a man should expose himself to witness pains, on whose removal or diminution he can exercise not any the slightest influence. No good is done to yourself, and none to others, by throwing yourself in the way of suffering, unmitigable in itself, or of which you are certain that it cannot be mitigated by you. Efficient benevolence is action ; it supposes the existence of good which is susceptible of increase, or of evil susceptible of being lessened or removed. The life painted by the poets of Elysium, where every man is sufficient to him self, must be dull and dreary indeed. It must be intolerable — it must be pure selfishness, disassociated from benevolence. Take the ele ments of pleasure away, and of what is left behind you may make happiness, when you can make a palace out of smoke and moonshine. With a man's elevation in society, the influ ence of his vices and virtues in society extends. The powers of beneficence and maleficence in crease together. The amours of Henry the Fourth produced an incalculable mass of misery. He made war upon Spain for the purpose of getting hold of the wife of another. He sacri ficed, every now and then, a portion of his army, for the sake of having his pleasure with his belle Gabrielle, Let those who will, give EFFECTIVE BENEVOLENCE — NEGATIVE. 179 their sympathy, their approbation, to such a nuisance as this monarch was ; but why should \ve? If he had lost an arm or a leg while pursuing his pleasures, great would have been the clamour, unbounded the expression of inte rest and sympathy. His partizans lost their lives by thousands, and what cared he ? To the power of situation the power of intel lect may be added, to give sanction to good or evil. Charles the Twelfth would have been more mischievous, had he not been mad. His obstinacy, in doing mischief by wholesale, was just as bad as Henry the Fourth's amours. For selfish enjoyments in one shape, Henry sacri ficed his thousands ; for selfish enjoyments in another shape, Charles did the like. When the laws of morality are understood, when the popular sanctions become properly enlightened, the misery-spreading freaks of monarchs will be no longer practised on mankind. As in the political field of action many of the claims of prudence are under the control of the legislator, so many of the claims of effective benevolence scarcely belong to the empire of the Deontologist private. It may not be out of place, however, to remark, that nothing but the light of utility will convey the patriot safely through the mazes of politics. Here, as elsewhere, the dogmatism about right 180 DEONTOLOGY. and rights has often led men astray, confused their honest purposes, and nullified their benevolently- intended heroism. Opposition, revolt, may, or may not be a public virtue. To allow of resist ance, on the score of a greater general utility to be obtained by resistance than by submission, is to put a buckler in the hands of liberty. To enjoin resistance, on the score of some imaginary injunction of the law of nature or revelation, is to place a torch in the hands of fanaticism. When effective benevolence is brought into the realms of Deontology, .when .the greatest good, the universal happiness, is made the central point round which all action revolvesj the golden era of moral science will commence. When its presence becomes universal, its influ ence omnipresent, the demand for punishment will be superseded, to a great extent, by the powers of reward. No pleasure will be unne cessarily wasted ; no pain unnecessarily inflicted. Hitherto a feeble ray of universal benevolence has thrown an uncertain glimmer over the field of human action. Sometimes it has been ab sorbed in unfruitful meditation ; at others it aas exhaled in periodical discourse, clouded too oft in mystery, or dispersed by the storms of selfish passions. The negative branch of effective benevolence is the abstinence from action, where that absti- EFFECTIVE BENEVOLENCE — NEGATIVE. 181 nence either removes a pain or creates a plea sure in the minds or persons of others. This branch of virtue presupposes the power of inflicting suffering or of conferring enjoyment; and its operation is to arrest the consequence of that disposition which, if allowed to act, would increase the sum of misery or lessen the sum of happiness. Its object is to arrest the word or the deed which would inflict evil on another, and, if possible, to check the thought which would create or excite the evil-inflicting or evil-intend ing word or deed. In order to give it efficiency, it will be well to trace up to their origin the motives which are unfriendly to this class of virtues. And they will be found to have their source — 1. In the interest of self, which may on some occasions be indeed in hostility with the benevolent sympathies, and on such occasions the benevolent sympathies must succumb. There is no help for it ; they are the weaker. Happily such cases are rare, for misery is sel dom inflicted without a reaction on the part of the sufferer. A man cannot hate another with out exciting some portion of hate in return. He cannot visit another with unfriendliness without curtailing the friendly affections of that other towards him. There is no voice, whether 182 DEONTOLOGY. of malevolence or benevolence, without an echo; no act, whether of good or evil, without a vibration. And this brings the benevolence of forbearance into the domains of self-regarding prudence, to which, after all, benevolence must make its final appeal. 2. The love of ease, heedlessness, is another cause of the absence of the abstential principle. There are men who will not take the trouble of Avoiding to give pain to others. They have no particular desire to intrude an annoyance, but will not bestir themselves to prevent that annoyance. Their laziness is, in a word, stronger than their benevolence. They would rather sleep on their pillows than rouse them selves to exertion. They give precipitate opinions to avoid the labors of investigation. They do hasty deeds, as if for the very purpose of compromising themselves. They do not choose to ask themselves whether they ought to doubt; still less are they willing to apply the old aphorism — ' If you doubt, abstain.' Their love of ease is flattered by a prompt decision— by getting rid of a question, the discussion or examination of which would have been a demand on their attention. They fancy they have re lieved themselves of an embarrassment by a peremptory verdict. 3. The interests of pride and vanity often EFFECTIVE BENEVOLENCE — NEGATIVE. 183 check the dictates of abstential benevolence. These may be called the interests of the trum pet, in whose sounds are drowned the voice of philanthropy. Pride and vanity dictate dogmatism. They assume superiority, and that superiority is always seeking to break out into speech. In some act of another they find cause for repre hension. Regardless of consequences, they reprehend. Benevolence would ask whether the repre hension was likely to do good either to the reprehender or the reprehended ; but pride and vanity are too proud and vain to seek or to take advice from morality. Sometimes they intrude inappropriate or ill- timed advice. There benevolence might have taught them to refrain. It might be a waste of words on their part, producing on the mind of the advised person an impression of uncom- pen sated pain; pain far greater than the plea sure which the pride or the vanity felt on giving their lecture. There are other occasions where pride and vanity volunteer information, neither desired nor welcomed. The information may look like a reproach to him whom it pretends to instruct; it often assumes the garb of assumption and 184 DEONTOLOGY. of dogmatism. What wonder it should be rebelled against ! In all these cases, and there are many more such, effective benevolence puts in its veto. 4. The interests of ill-will or antipathy. These take many forms, and require to be doubly bridled, for they are pernicious to both parties, and leave on every side a balance of evil. And they are the more pernicious, be cause they do not always exhibit the malevo lence of their origin. They are sometimes moved by the rival posi tion of another. There is a clashing of interests, producing coldness, dislike, or hatred. Hence a desire to inflict pain upon a rival. Ill-will may have grown out of injuries done by another. He may have interfered with your love of ease ; he may have wounded your pride or your vanity; he may have wronged your friend ; he may have misrepresented your poli tical or religious opinions. These are no reasons that you should do him mischief. Morality requires, your own interest requires, that you should forbear from doing him mischief. Cast up the results — the pains of ill-will, the plea sures of revenge, and then the re-action of revenge upon yourself, and possibly upon others. You will find the balance against you, as EFFECTIVE BENEVOLENCE— NEGATIVE. 185. / concerns your own account—the self-regarding account; and as respects the object of your ill-will, it is an account of suffering without deduction. Besides, you are giving evidence not only of immorality, but of weakness. You have no power over the mind of him who is obnoxious to you : so you exhibit, at the same time, a want of self-control and a malignity of intention, — proofs of mental weakness and moral defects. In difference of taste, ill-will may find ano ther motive for acts which benevolence would check. Such differences have often been made the plea for words of hatred and deeds of hatred. And into no part of the field of action has malevolence rushed with greater malignity. Here, especially, is there a demand for the avoidance of pain-giving. The demand is, indeed, everywhere where the pain-giving is useless or baneful, and it is eminently so here, In fine, effective benevolence, in its negative requirements, exacts that, on all and every occasion, the infliction of evil shall be abstained from, except where its infliction shuts out a greater evil, or brings with it a more than coun terbalancing good. Its action being the avoidance of annoyance to others, it is important, for the correct and complete estimate of its operation, that all the 186 DEONTOLOGY. sources of annoyance should be studied. In order to provide the remedy, the cause must be known. And this is the more necessary, as there are multitudinous evils, of whose exist ence, or at all events of their pain-giving con sequences, men seem to be too little aware. Consult the various classes of pain and plea sure ; consult their modifications ; look to the annoyances of which the bodily senses are susceptible, those, of course, which it does not belong to penal legislation to visit — the pains of privation, the pleasures of good reputation ; in a word, the whole store-house of satisfaction and of suffering. Take into account the general susceptibilities of men, and, as far as can be ascertained, the peculiar susceptibilities of the individual. Secondary virtues, growing out of this branch of Deontology, are the virtues of good-breeding, which correspond pretty nearly to that class which the French call ' la petite morale.' / Good- breeding is that deportment, on occasions of inferior, and when separately taken, of trivial importance, by which those acts are abstained from which give annoyance to others. Where, on similar occasions, the acts are done which give pleasure to others, they belong to the positive or active, not the negative or abstential branch. But it is to the latter that most of the EEFECTIVE BENEVOLENCE — NEGATIVE. 187 laws of good -breeding must be referred, and here the demand for its exercise is constant, and the field of its action wide. The most ordinary and indispensable personal prudence operates as a bridle upon rudeness and ill manners. The disposition to contribute, in all unforbidden shapes, to the gratification of others, and to refrain from all that can annoy them, is true politeness. 188 DEONTOLOGY. CHAPTER XIV. EFFECTIVE BENEVOLENCE — POSITIVE. THE negative branch of effective benevolence comprises, as we have seen, those acts, or rather that absence of action, by which the giving pain to others is avoided ; the positive branch consists of those acts by which pleasure is com municated. This branch is far less extensive than the other, inasmuch as the powers pos sessed (by the majority of the community at least) to communicate happiness to others, are far less extensive than the powers of causing misery to others. Nearly every man has over nearly every other man around him the power of inflicting injury in various forms. There are many pains which a man can cause another to suffer which have no corresponding pleasures that he can offer to that other to enjoy. We have no sense which may not be offended at the will of another, but those senses are not equally subject to him who seeks to gratify them against or without our will. Any man may strike, or wound another, but it is not the privilege of every man to be able to add to another's happi- EFFECTIVE BENEVOLENCE — POSITIVE. 189 ness. The limitation of this power is the ne cessary consequence of the fact, that man is, to a very great extent, the creator and the guardian of his own happiness. That portion for which he depends on others is small — that for which he depends only on himself is great ; and in this power over his own happiness, that happi ness greatly consists. Who would judge of pains and pleasures as accurately as he who experiences them ? Who, if it were possible, would put the dominion of his enjoyments and sufferings into another's hands ? To whose never-ceasing watchfulness — to whose self-de voted sympathies — to wrhose omniscient wis dom, would any man give over, for a single day, all the sources of pains and pleasures within and without him? One moment of forgetful- ness, one moment of malevolence, one moment of ignorance, and the fabric of felicity might be shattered, Happy, indeed, is it for man that he is the master of his own well-being, and that, with few and rare exceptions, he has no body to thank but himself if he fail to obtain it. But this positive effective benevolence — what does it demand but deprivation ? In as far as it is called into action, is it not impoverishment / Does it not take away more than it substitutes in return ? Not so ; for then it gets into the regions of imprudence ; and prudence is man's 190 DEONTOLOGY. primary virtue. Nothing is gained to happiness if prudence loses more than benevolence wins. There is, however, a large portion of benevo lence which may be called into activity without any sacrifice at all. Men there have been, and are, who deem all services done to others as something lost to themselves ; — a narrow and a baneful sentiment ; for it is the lot of every one to have the power of conferring favors at no cost at all, or at so small a cost as not to be worth a calculation. To make a favor of that which should be a spontaneous, or at all events a wil ling contribution to the happiness of another, is, in common parlance, to give evidence of a low- toned spirit of philanthropy, while, on the other hand, no beneficence looks so bright in the popular eyes, none is, in fact, so praiseworthy as that which avoids the parade of its sacrifices. And the popular sanction is here in accordance with the Deontological principle. Benevolence and beneficence are maximized when, at the least expence to himself, a man produces the greatest quantity of happiness to others. To lose sight of his own happiness would not be virtue, but folly. His own hap piness forms, or ought to form, as large a por tion of the whole mass of happiness spread among the community, as does the happiness of any other individual. EFFECTIVE BENEVOLENCE — POSITIVE, 191 Now, suppose any man to confer upon others a smaller portion of happiness than he himself sacrificed — that is, suppose him, in order to give a certain amount of pleasure to another, to give up a greater amount of pleasure of his own, this would not be virtue — it would be folly. It would not be effective benevolence, it would be miscalculation ; by it the whole amount of happiness would clearly be diminished. This, indeed, is a course of action which could not intentionally have place. No sane person wastes, or desires to waste, happiness, still less his own happiness. Every man's necessary impulse is towards the economy of happiness. If he made a sacri fice of his own happiness to the happiness of others, it could by possibility be in no other in terest than that of economy ; for unless in some shape or other he derived more pleasure from the sacrifice than he expected to derive in ab staining from making the sacrifice, he would not, he could not make it. Suppose other plea sures equal — that is, the pleasures sacrificed and the pleasures conferred — suppose nothing is lost in the transfer, then come the pleasures of sympathy, pleasures which form as large a portion of a man's happiness as any merely self-regarding pleasure. They turn the scale ; and of their magnitude the man who seeks 192 '. DEONTOLOGY. them is the most competent, not to say the only judge. His miscalculation does not alter the ques tion. The province of Deontology is to teach him a proper arithmetic, is to lay before him a fit estimate of pain and pleasure — a budget of receipt and disbursement, out of every opera tion of which he is to draw a balance of good. And here, be it remarked by the way, that tne Deontological teacher, whether engaged in discourse or in writing, is himself an example of the application of the principle of positive effective benevolence. Let his exertions be en couraged by the thought, that he is perhaps producing more happiness at less expense than could be produced by any other means. At a cost of a few well-timed words is he not ex panding the domains of happiness ? Are not the truths, which he circulates at the waste of a little breath, or at the trouble of recording them on the permanent tablets of the press, are they not likely to extend the dominions of felicity into regions bounded only by that por tion of infirmity which must hang about the destinies of mortal man ? It is a positive act of effective benevolence to sow seeds of useful fruits, or beautiful flowers, where none were ever sown before ; but how much more effi ciently benevolent is he who sows those seeds EFFECTIVE BENEVOLENCE POSITIVE. 193 out of which happiness directly springs — hap piness prolific, multiform, permanent. Nor let it be forgotten that, in proportion to the poverty of the receiver, will be the value of the gift conferred. The greater the want, the greater the boon will be. Now certain it is that erroneous standards of action have pro duced much moral poverty, much misery in the world — poverty and misery which the intelli gent moralist is called upon to remove. What higher mission than his? What nobler pursuit? Rendering services of incalculable value to others, he establishes a claim — a claim which will be felt to be irresistible — of other services to be rendered to himself in return. He exer cises power, in itself a source of pleasure, — that power, of all power the most delightful, the power of beneficence. He exercises it towards all, without distinction or exception. In this there is no sacrifice, no sacrifice of self-regarding interest ; and by these and simi lar means every man may advance the progress, and accelerate the triumphs of happiness. Every man has more or less of time on his hands. On many hands how heavily it hangs ! Would they improve it, would they enjoy it? Let them engage it in beneficence ! The field of beneficence is the whole world, those parts of it more particularly in which a VOL. i. o 194 DEONTOLOGY. man exercises his peculiar influence— whether personal, domestic, or social. The occasions it may find for its exercise are somewhat de pendent on these influences. Towards inferiors and equals the occasions are permanent, towards superiors transitory. In the practical part of these volumes, these relations will come particu larly under review. ANALYSIS OF VIRTUES AND VICES. 195 CHAPTER XV. ANALYSIS OF VIRTUES AND VICES. THE ground has now been cleared, and the foundation laid for the moral edifice. What remains to be done is, to sweep away the surrounding rubbish, or to take from the ruins such portions as will assist the builder in the erection of the temple of virtue. Wherever prudence presents itself, wherever effective benevolence presents itself, they will be rescued from the huge heaps which have hitherto en cumbered the ground of ethics. Where neither of these is discoverable, let who will turn the impostor virtue to account. No acceptance will it find here. And so as to vice. No quarrel have we with any action that neither injures the actor himself, nor any body else; in a word, that takes nothing away from happiness; still less with any action, which, be it called by what name it may, leaves a balance of enjoyment on the whole. Virtues and vices are voluntary habits. If N / they are not voluntary, the words of the moralist might as well be flung to the winds. To the 196 DEONTOLOGY. *"- two branches of virtue, prudence and bene volence, correspond two branches of vices ; — Imprudence, the vice in a man which is primarily hurtful to himself, — Improbity, the vice which is hurtful primarily to others. It matters little in what order the seHVcalled virtues or vices present themselves. There is no marshalling them ; they are susceptible of no arrangement; they are a disorderly body, whose members are frequently in hostility with one another. Most of them consist of a portion of good, a portion of evil, and a portion of matter indifferent, Most of them are characterised by that vagueness which is a convenient instrument for the poetical, but dangerous or useless to the practical moralist. The three commonly called cardinal virtues, however, naturally present themselves first to the mind. To what action does the praise of fortitude com monly attach ? To that by which a man volun tarily exposes himself to a danger he might have avoided, — to danger, to bodily pain, to death. In proportion to the magnitude of the danger — to the intensity and duration of the pain, or the probability of death, is he considered to possess the virtue of fortitude. Is it desirable for the ultimate good of society that he should so expose himself? In this is FORTITUDE. 197 the measure of all merit. Will he advance his own well-being or the well-being of others ? If the two interests, his own and that of others are incompatible, to which is it desirable the preference should be given? This may be difficult, but too difficult to know, yet this is something to be known, and if it can be known it is well worth knowing. The thing to be purchased is benefit to a man himself or to others. The danger to which he is -i \ exposed is the price he would pay for the bene- . * ^ fit. Is the benefit worth the cost ? This is the question, the only question deserving an inquiry or a thought. Whether his exposing himself . to the supposed danger is an act of fortitude or ^ not, is a query not worth the words expended in the proposing it. And the question is not merely useless, it is positively pernicious ; for such questions only throw men's ideas into confusion, entangle their minds in irrelevant discussions, and lead them away from the proper, the only proper topic of inquiry, namely, the union between interests and duties. Now, — suppose an act injurious to those inter ests, and that this act is understood to merit the appellation of fortitude. What is the practical consequence ? That fortitude, being a virtue, the injurious act is that which ought to be done. 98 DEONTOLOGY. And suppose the line of conduct most condu cive to the general happiness, not to deserve the appellation of fortitude ? What then ? Why if fortitude be a virtue, the act which most pro motes the general happiness must be an act of folly or of vice. Wonderful is the absurdity, dense the blind ness, palpable the self-contradiction of the Oxford Instructor on the subject of Fortitude. According to him, on what does it depend? On the magnitude of the pain which a man continues to endure ? No such thing. On the magnitude of the danger, that is, the eventual suffering to which he voluntarily exposes him self? No, not that. Upon what then ? Upon the nature of the occasion on which the suffering is endured or the danger incurred. If the occasion is approved by the Instructor, there shall be fortitude ; if the occasion have the ill-fortune not to have his sanction, no fortitude shall there be, In battle or otherwise, a man risks, or even loses his life. Was he a brave man ? Was his act an act of fortitude? Go and ask the Instructor, and he will not tell you till he knows on which side he fought. Inform me, he will say, of the occasion of his death. If I approve of the occasion, then it is an act of fortitude ; if not, not. The Instructor makes four special and un- FORTITUDE. 199 doubted exceptions, — self-slayers, duellists, robbers, and men who devote themselves to danger or death in defence of their liberty. These are not men of fortitude ; their doings deserve not any of its praise. A man who puts an end to his own existence, cannot be a man of fortitude. Would you know why ? Because suicide is unlawful. A man who slays another, or is slain by another in a duel, cannot be a man of fortitude. Why ? Because he ought not to have fought. A man dies defending his own liberty ; he must be a coward; justice was not on his side. A robber plays the hero. Is he a courageous man ? Not he ; for what business had he to be on the highway? But if consistency were looked for, if in ortho dox or fashionable faith, nonsense were an impe diment to the reception of that faith, one might suggest that it would be well to apply the princi ple to practice. Among the whole tribe of con querors, where would the man of fortitude be found ? Your Alexanders, your Caesars, your Ghenghis Khans, your Napoleons, what were they all? Any thing but men of fortitude. When the protection afforded to absurdity is such that no one dares open his mouth against it,— its march is bold and imposing. You may 200 DEONTOLOGY. grant or deny, at your pleasure, the praise of fortitude to those who X'oluntarily thrust themselves upon danger or death; they shall be called brave men, or cowards according to your bidding. Temperance has for its object the pleasures of sense. Though commonly used to express abstinence from the enjoyments of one or two of the senses, there seems no sufficient reason for such a limitation to the term. The question of virtue must be decided by the influence of the enjoyments of sense on ourselves and others. Intemperance, when mischievous to a man himself, is a breach of prudence ; when mis chievous to others, it is a breach of benevo lence. Preponderant enjoyment, or preponder ant suffering, is the only standard by which the moral merits of fruition can be estimated. Abstinence, which leaves no balance of plea sure, partakes not of the character of virtue ; enjoyment, which leaves no balance of pain, cannot justly be stigmatised with the reproach of vice. There exists in the world a great unwilling ness to allow a man to be the curator of his own pleasures ; there is a vehement disposition to decide on what, in the breast of another man, may be allowed to be a pleasure, and what not. TEMPERANCE. 201 ; The words impropriety, unlawfulness, and such like, are flung at particular actions, in order to excite odium, as if they were evidence of de pravity ; such words being, in fact, only a part and portion of that phraseology, by which a man seeks to shelter his own dogmatism from the analysis which the doctrines of utility would apply to it. Prudence and effective benevolence, it cannot be too often repeated, being the only two intrin sically useful virtues, all other virtues must derive their value from them, and be subservient to them. Is justice, then, a subservient and inferior virtue ? And if so, to which is it subordinate ? Before the art of logic was understood, and especially before the business of arrangement, in any thing like correctness or completeness, was accomplished, ideas respecting virtue, and names designating those ideas, were introduced. The relations between virtue and virtue were vague and obscure ; the descriptions of them confused — the points of coincidence and of dif ference indeterminate or undetermined. Logic ally speaking, they were disparate ; mathernatic- allj^speaking, they were incommensurable. /Of the virtues, the Aristotelians introduced the definitions and classification we have seen. Of these virtues several have been divided into 202 DEONTOLOGY. • species. But, on examination, it will be found that under the same generic names virtues are classed which have no assignable relation to each other ; and some, in which the character of the genus under which they are arranged is not discoverable. The modifications put forward under the head of one virtue, not unfrequently belong to another, and on a glance at the whole, tlie appearance is one of strange entanglement and perplexity. Though the Linnaeus of Natu ral History has appeared in the world, and restored its chaos into order and harmony, the Linnaeus of Ethics is yet to come. Justice, under the system of utility, is a modification of benevolence ; it belongs to the present work wherever the political sanction, or the power of the law does not apply ; it be longs to it wherever the sanction of moral obli gation is unenforced by penal visitation. The inadequacy and imperfection of the poli tical or legal sanction is experienced in a con siderable part of the field of morality, and a demand will be created for the dictates of the moral sanction, as guided by utility, in the fol lowing cases : — Where the legal sanction is silent, or, in other words, makes no provision for the case in point. Where the legal sanction is inconsistent with, or opposed to the greatest happiness principle. JUSTICE. 203 Where the dictates of the legal sanction are confused, or unintelligible. Where they are impracticable. In all these cases, the dictates of justice will be the dictates of benevolence, and the dictates of benevolence the dictates of utility. It would assist clearness of conception, if the word probity could take place of the term jus tice, with which it is pretty completely synony mous ; at least, if there be a difference, it is rather grammatical than ethical ; for though a man says with propriety, I will do you justice, he cannot say, I will do you probity, though every act of injustice done would be an act of improbity, and, conversely, every act of impro bity an act of injustice. The word j ustice is clogged with other signi fications, which render it less efficient as an ethical term. It may, for example, be employed as a substitute for the term judicature. He by whom the powers of judicature are adminis tered, is said to administer justice. But on such an occasion it is never said that he admin isters probity, nor does the association of pro bity necessarily attach to the phrase. Hence a great evil, and a source of error ; for if, in the exercise of his office, he be most truly and manifestly chargeable with improbity, not the less will the language be employed that he 204 DEONTOLOGY. administers justice. The improbity will still be clothed in the garb of justice. Himself and his friends will say he administers justice, and it will be a matter of great difficulty and perplex ity for those who think ill of him to impugn the phraseology. Yet by no one will he be said to administer probity, scarcely by any one will it be said that he exercises probity. This is one of the thousand cases in which vague and unde fined expressions become places of shelter for insincerity and immorality. The pleasures and pains of amity are those of the popular or moral sanction, in miniature ; — in the one case their source is a determinate indi vidual, in the other an indefinite multitude. When is it desirable that the pleasures of amity should be reaped ? Whenever they may be reaped without the production of preponder ant evil, — without violation of the laws of self- regarding prudence. To what length may their pursuit be carried ? To exactly the length which is consistent with the cardinal virtues of prudence and benevolence, and it will be found that between these and the pleasures and pains of amity there is rarely any competition. / To obtain the favor — the amity of another, the obvious course is to do him services — these ser vices limited only by the considerations of bene volence and prudence^ The limits which effec- AMITY. 205 tive benevolence applies to the exercise of amity are the same as apply to the pursuit of wealth. If the services derived from him whose amity you court be the conferring on you a portion of wealth, — the pursuit of wealth is the pursuit of amity : and in precisely so far as the pursuit of wealth, with the enjoyments and exemptions de rivable from it, is repugnant to benevolence, so is the pursuit of amity. The pleasures derivable from this pursuit have this distinctive and interesting character : — that prudence and benevolence are almost equally concerned in their production. For however selfish the desire may be, — how ever unrelieved by the social sympathy, the effects of it are not the less purely beneficial to the parties concerned. The interest of him who courts the amity of another, may be served or not served as may happen — the person courted has his interest served to an extent nearly equal to that he would have obtained for himself if he had himself sought the pleasure conferred. And though it is not sympathy, — not benevolence that has produced the pleasure, yet it is not the less produced — and thus the good, though not arising from a primary virtue, is as valuable as if it arose from it. The sole value of benevolence itself consists in its ten dency and aptitude to produce beneficence, 206 DEONTOLOGY. and no evil can grow from the excess of the friendly affections, except when they interfere with the primary virtues. Proportioned to the value of the services which a man is deemed able and willing to confer on others, will be the number of competitors in those services. In this, as in every other case, competition may produce jealousy, and each competitor who is believed to have obtained a greater share than another, may be to that other an object of envy. This envy will endeavor to produce a reaction of ill-will on the person who is the object of envy, and one of its immediate effects, will be to lower the envied receiver of favors, in the eyes of him who confers them. Nevertheless, there exists a tribunal, that which deals out the decisions of good repute, or general esteem, before which this contention for benefits is always carried on; and every man is a member of this tribunal who chooses to take a part in its awards. Before this tribunal every man who seeks to detract from the merits of another man acts the part of an informer; and his conduct is usually attributed to a sin ister and disreputable motive. Be his motives what they may, dishonorable or dislogistic phrases will probably attach to his conduct, and thus the popular sanction be brought to bear upon the self-regarding impulse. AMITY. 207 Servility is one of the terms most commonly employed on these occasions. Its synonymes and quasi-synonymes are very numerous, and the im pression it conveys is of an exceedingly vague and indeterminate character. So much the worse ; no precise idea being attached to it, the accusation becomes the more impressive. If closely looked to, it will be found to mean the habit of rendering to a supe rior, services which, according to the received notions of propriety, ought not to be rendered. As a rule of conduct, the so often repeated prin ciple of balancing pleasures and pains will apply here, as every where. To render to every man every possible ser vice, where neither prudence nor benevolence has aught to object, is the obvious dictate and duty of beneficence ; and in the case before us, the dictates of benevolence are in their full force without any counteracting or diminishing force on the side of prudence. But here, as on most other occasions, are two sets of antagonizing forces, the impelling and the restraining ; the only limits to the proper influ ence of the compelling force being that which is exercised by the restraining power. The virtue of beneficence, though its objects embrace all mankind, can be exercised to a very limited extent, and as applied to any single indi- 208 DEONTOLOGY, vidual yet narrower is its sphere of action. And this is well ; for if every man were disposed to sacrifice his own enjoyments to the enjoyments of others, it is obvious the whole sum of enjoy ment would be diminished — nay destroyed. The result would not be the general happiness, but the general misery. Prudence therefore sets its limits to benevolence, and those limits do not, on ordinary occasions, embrace a large space. In the case before us, /prudence so far from prohibiting, prescribes the obligation of render* ing services to the superior — services in the ut most quantity that can be rendered under a sufficient assurance that the value of the ser vices received in return will not be less than that of the suffering, self-denial, or sacrifice in curred, in order to obtain them. Prudence makes a sort of commercial bargain — the sort of bargain on which all commerce is founded. The expenditure is expected to bring back something more than its cost.^ No outlay is detrimental that returns an equivalent — no ex- pence fails to be beneficial, which brings back an equivalent and something more. Here then is prudence acting in two directions — prescribing expenditure, in as far as it pro mises a beneficial return, inhibiting expenditure where the beneficial return cannot be reasonably anticipated. But here, as elsewhere, no law of AMITY. 209 benevolence must be violated while prudence seeks the beneficial return in question. And how are the dictates of self- regarding prudence to be ascertained ? by what are they determined ? By the balance of an account em bracing the different heads under which plea sures and pains are capable of being arranged. Prudence on all occasions supposes and requires the sacrifice of pleasures and exemptions on the one hand, to pleasures and exemptions on the other. Between the rival amounts the decision must lie, and the decision of wisdom must be with the larger of the two. In the present case the rivalry is between the pleasures of amity and the pains of the popular sanction. There are certain services rendered by which a man exposes himself to the loss of repu tation, even services which are by no means inconsistent with the primary virtues. Fashion makes multitudinous exceptions which it would be difficult to get confirmed by any correct views of the demands of prudence and benevolence. In different stages of civilization these exceptions have undergone many modifications. The higher the scale of rank, — the greater the distance be tween the most elevated and the least elevated spheres, — the less has fashion introduced of restraint. In proportion as equality takes pos session of society is the latitude allowed to such VOL. I. P 210 DEONTOLOGY. services diminished, and the restrictions upon them increased. Going back into the field of time, we shall find that deportment, and espe cially in language, was in use, of a character so obsequious, that it would not now be tolerated at all — that habits of submission and expressions of humiliation were then deemed proper — pru dent — and even demanded by good breeding, which now would be placed to the account of servility, meanness, and even baseness, and draw down on him who should venture to use them a full measure of popular contempt. Go forth into the field of space ; visit any Maho- medan — any oriental nation. In these countries, under their governments, the distance between the highest and the lowest degree is almost infi nite, and between the different degrees enormous. Thus no measure of obsequiousness is out of place — none is checked by opinion. To those in the lower ranks self-abasement is self-preser vation, and the most prostrate servility is de manded by prudence. Bending, or as the phrase is, cringing or fawn ing to his superior, the same man is stiff, and even insolent to his inferior. It is an every day case and a very natural one ; for the suffering to which he subjects himself in the one case, he seeks to counterbalance by enjoyments of the same character in the other. But by thus gra- PRIDE AND VANITY. 211 tifying his pride he provokes enmity, and through enmity ill offices, and through ill offices suffering in all imaginable shapes. Is he on the whole a gainer by this indulgence ? That will depend partly on his idiosyncratic taste, and partly upon accident. Pride and vanity are dispositions of mind not necessarily or even ordinarily manifested by sin gle acts. So intimate is the relation between pride and vanity, that to uncover them together is likely to facilitate correct ideas of both. Both are the desire of esteem, taking somewhat dif ferent directions, and employing different means of gratification. To the proud man and the vain man the esteem of those on whom they believe their well-being to depend, is the common object of pursuit. And in both cases the important question is, — This pride, this vanity, — is it of the nature of virtue, or of vice ? If of virtue, of what virtue ? — if of vice, of what vice ? In the proud man, the desire of esteem is accompanied with contempt, or disesteem for those whose esteem he desires to obtain. In the vain man this is not the case. The value of the esteem being less in the eyes of the proud than of the vain man, a greater portion of that esteem is required to give the proud man equal gratification with that 212 . DEONTOLOGY. which the vain man would receive from a lesser portion. And thus the state of the proud man's mind is generally that of dissatisfaction — a dis- ,?atisfaction which may be read even in his countenance. Melancholy and malevolence, one or both, are thence the usual companions of pride, sometimes a(Hing as causes, sometimes as effects of pride, sometimes in both characters. Hilarity, on the contrary, is the common accompaniment of vanity — hilarity and oftentimes benevolence. From a small manifestation of esteem, vanity re ceives a great gratification ; and the smaller the manifestation the more easily obtained ; hence the more frequently, and the more frequently, the more frequent are the causes of exhili- ration. Pride is naturally conjoined with taciturnity ; vanity with talkativeness. The proud man sits still and waits for those demonstrations of esteem which he desires to obtain. Their value to him depends on their being spontaneous. He will not call, or at least will not appear to call for them ; he will rather tarry for their arrival, and thus must possess the faculty of self-command to enable him to do so. Esteem is the food he hungers for, and his meal must be a full one — but he is able to fast. Not so the vain man. His appetite is still PRIDE AND VANITY. 213 keener than that of the proud man. No quan tity of its food will definitely satiate it, though a small quantity will gratify, and for a time will satisfy it. He therefore goes from door to door and at every door craves those supplies for which he has a perpetually self-renewing hun ger. Taken by itself, pride is scarcely ever used but in a bad sense, as descriptive of vice ; with an adjunct it may be used in a good sense, and become a virtue. Witness honest, becom ing, dignified pride. But even here a feeling attaches to it, that such phraseology is not strictly proper, and a sense of something figu rative or rhetorical hangs about it. But as for the adjective proud, when applied to a man, the idea it conveys is unfavorable. When proud is employed to denote the cast of a man's mind, intimation is given that that part of his mind is vicious. A proud day, a proud situation, may be used; and thus, indirectly, you may connect a man with an event, and disconnect him from the idea of vicious pride. Vanity is still worse dealt with. It can hardly be ascribed to a man without making him the object of contempt and derision, and a fit object too. It would scarcely be possible to speak, certainly it would not be possible to speak with propriety, of honest, becoming, dignified 214 DEONTOLOGY. vanity. A proud day you may have, and think well of such a day ; but you could not do so, were you to call it a vain day. But for practical purposes, the great object is to distinguish what there is of virtue and what of vice in these qualities of pride and vanity. If there be virtue, it is prudence, bene volence, or beneficence. If there be vice, it belongs either to imprudence or maleficence. And thus, and for the first time, perhaps, shall we find clear ideas attaching to appellations which are, every day in the year, in the mouth of every body. Were the principles of morality thoroughly understood and obeyed ; in other words, were the popular sanction in every respect that which, for the interests of mankind, it is desirable it should become, any portion remaining of pride would not be in the nature of vice. But as it is, where public opinion has not utility for its foundation, pride must frequently be classified among vices. The quantity of virtue or of vice growing out of pride and vanity, seems to depend in some manner on the station occupied in the scale of society by the proud or vain man. In the station of the ruling few, pride is more likely to dispose the mind to vice than to virtue ; but not so vanity. Pride, when it runs into vice, is the charac- PRIDE AND VANITY. 215 teristic vice of the ruling orders, they being, from their situation, less dependent than other men on spontaneous services; to a man so elevated, spontaneous services from others be come comparatively objects of indifference, and he is consequently indisposed to obtain those services at the cost of any services rendered by himself, even the inexpensive services of urban ity. Pride, therefore, in such elevated situations, draws men away from benevolence and bene ficence, and presents these virtues as rivals to the self-regarding interest. Vanity suggests another course. Its ever- craving appetite demands continued services, the services which manifest esteem. And here its tendency is towards benevolence. Thus acts seemingly benevolent, acts bearing upon them the impress of social sympathy, whether reflec tive or sentimental, may have their source in the self-regarding affection of vanity. The acts being produced, the object is gained to human happiness. Will not vanity, then, an swer the purposes of utility, by producing the good which utility proposes as its end ? No ! not unless opinion, not unless the popular sanction be, on all points, in accordance with the teachings of utility. But the display of vanity, on whatever titles to esteem it be founded, produces competition, 216 DEONTOLOGY. increasing with the increase of that esteem of which display is made, and this competition produces uneasiness.£jVanity in one breast calls into existence, and thence into action, the emotions, the affections, the passions of envy and jealousy, in many breastslj In elevated life, the higher a man's station the less likely is it to awaken envy or jealousy on the part of the subject many ; for envy and jealousy can hardly exist except where com petition exists, and the greater the distance between rank and rank, the less room is there for competition. At the same time, the higher a man's station the wider is the field in which he can exercise his beneficence; and in so far as,/ by acts of beneficence, his vanity seeks its gratification,/ the esteem which he obtains serves to counter balance, if not to outweigh, the pains and dan gers which are produced by the envy and jealousy of others, whether as acting upon him, or upon those in whose minds the envy and jealousy have place. The effect will be different among the subject many ; for as the power of beneficence is less, the envy and jealousy will be greater. Here the assumption of superiority, under the influ ence of vanity, will be more offensive, and * the best wrestler on the green' may excite PRIDE AND VANITY, 217 feelings of envy and jealousy in the breasts of all the other wrestlers, while he can produce no counterbalancing pleasure. Pain he may clearly awaken ; but what sensible addition to happiness can he make to the happiness of any individual not comprised within his own domes tic circle ? The vain man exaggerates to himself the value of the services of others, and is occupied in undue exertions to obtain them. The proud man diminishes, to his own mind, the value of the services of others, and measures his right to claim them by the inverse ratio of his need of them, — of the esteem in which he holds them. Activity is the companion of vanity ; immobility of pride. Every addition to the affection of vanity adds something to the power of sympathy towards others. Every addition to the affection of pride excludes a portion of sympathy towards others. Yet the denial of the good offices sought will awaken the hostility both of the proud and the vain man. The proud man's hostility will be more open, undisguised, and conspicuous. He gives you to understand that he cares not whether your dispositions towards him be friendly or adverse. His importance is such, that, from respect or fear, others are engaged to render him the services, or more services, than 218 DEONTOLOGY. you can offer him : but the vain man appears to exercise no despotism over you in order to obtain your good-will ; the greater his vanity, the greater his desire, the more strenuous his efforts to secure it. Pride is thus accompanied with a sense of independence ; vanity, not. The proud man is persuaded that he shall receive from others as much respect as he stands in need of; he there fore will not take the trouble of courting them, that is, of employing exertion in order to admi nister to their gratification. He will not, him self, put forward the titles he believes himself to possess to their esteem. He assumes that they are obvious, and will be recognized as a matter of course. In as far as he succeeds, his pride conveys to the minds of others a sense of his own importance; he causes them to think that, in some way or other, their comfort depends upon his favor, which favor, he would have them believe, is difficult to gain. Hence, on their part, there exists towards him a sort of fear — the fear of not being able to gain it. Now this fear is necessarily attended with suffering. Of this suffering he has himself a perception, yet will not do what depends upon him to remove or to lessen it. By mixing condescension with his pride, he might lessen it. By laying aside his pride, and dealing with PRIDE AND VANITY. 219 them on a footing of equality, he might remove it altogether. On the whole, then, vanity is more nearly allied to benevolence ; pride to self-regard and malevolence. The vain man, feeling himself comparatively ill-assured of the esteem he desires, is propor tionally anxious to do his best to obtain it; he endeavors to display those qualities which are likely to win it ; and seeking to gather the good-will of others, he must sow the seeds which produce it. And the object of the dis play he makes will usually be, in some degree at least, effected. He will excite some admi ration; admiration brings surprise, surprise awakens curiosity, in whose gratification there is pleasure. There are two causes, however, by which this effect is liable, not only to be counteracted and diminished, but even to be reversed. First, Vwhen the superiority displayed is such as to produce humiliation, or a painful sense of infe riority, in the breasts of those before whom the display is made ; and, secondly, this effect will be heightened if the endowment displayed be one in which" any particular competition exists between the persons exhibiting it, and him before whom it is exhibited.] When this is the case, both prudence and 220 DEONTOLOGY. benevolence concur in recommending that the exhibition should be abstained from ; prudence, becausej,hej>assions of envy and jealousy will awaken ill-will towards himself.; ill-will, tend ing to ill offices or to the abstinence from friendly offices ; and benevolence, because the exhibition will produce pain in the breast of another. Associated with the subject of pride are many terms, the value and bearing of which can only be determined by the application of the great principles so constantly brought forward in this volume. Meanness has for its opposite not so much pride as a compound appellation — elevation of mind — high-mindedness. But there is, and must be, much of indistinctness in these qualities. Pride, separately taken, is rather dyslogistic ; high-mindedness, eulogistic. So again, humility is supposed to be creditable ; meanness discreditable. And the obscurity is much increased by the sense which has been given to these terms by writers on religion. Independence of mind is another term suscep tible of very different interpretations. The rule, the test, the standard, must be the conducive- ness of these qualities, in every particular case, to happiness, the happiness of the individual and of the rest of mankind. Every thing else is a mere fruitless question about words, of no ENVY AND JEALOUSY. 221 practical, no real importance ; a question as to phrases whose meanings are perpetually liable to change and perpetually changing ; and whose discussion, unless with a reference to some rule of right and wrong, is mere waste of time and labor. CEor~the purpose of exposition, then, as well as for the purposes of instruction, the sole effective mode is to ascertain the association of moral terms with the terms of pain and plea sure. Apply any other test to vanity, apply any other test to pride, and it will be seen, that to their import and their value this is the only key. And what is true here is true in every other part of the moral region. Envy and jealousy are neither virtues nor vices. They are pains. Envy is pain emanating from the contempla tion of pleasure possessed by another, especially when that pleasure is derived from a source 'whence the envious person desired to derive it ; if the desire was accompanied with the expec tation that it would have been so derived, the pain becomes stronger still ; and strongest of all when he supposes that the possession of the pleasure by another has led to his exclusion from it. 222 DEONTOLOGY. Jealousy is "pain — the pain of apprehension derived from the same or a similar cause. Prudence and benevolence are equally con cerned in suppressing both envy and jealousy : prudence, for the purpose of ridding ourselves of the pains they cause us ; benevolence, inas much as envy and jealousy are associated with the, desire to rid ourselves of the pains they create, by evil deeds to others. Envy and jealousy are very closely allied to, and very instrumental in creating maleficent dispositions, and thence maleficent actions. The disposition, without the action, is indeed not a vice ; it is an infirmity ; but infirmity is a soil in which vice is very easily planted, and in which it very luxuriantly grows. HUME'S VIRTUES. 223 CHAPTER XVI. HUME'S VIRTUES. BUT, (inj)rder to discover how vague are the ideas of virtue, and how unsatisfactory the definitions, even emanating from jninds of high intellectual capacity, where the standard of virtue has either not been discovered^ or not employed, it will be well worth whilerieven at the expense of some repetition, jtp go over jthe ground, f accompanied by Mr Hume's list of virtues ; and, upon a close examination, we shall learn how easily a scene of confusion, entan glement, and perplexity, may be reduced to order, harmony, and beauty, by the instruments which, in the shape of prudence and bene volence, utility has put into our hands. And this course seems the more desirable, because it is not long since |the Edinburgh Reviewers, in calling attention to Hume's classification of the virtues, seemed to consider that he had done every thing which it was necessary to do, in order to introduce a perfect moral system, j There is a fundamental objection to his clas sification of the virtues into useful and agreeable 224 DEONTOLOGY. qualities. Useful is here altogether ambiguous; it may mean conducive to pleasure — it may mean conducive to any other end. Usefulness has no value, but in so far as it is pleasure- producing or pain-preventing, leading, on the whole, to a balance of happiness, calculated not only out of the pleasure which is adjacent, but of that which is remote ; not only out of present, but of future pleasure. Strange indeed is it that moralists are so afraid of the word pleasure ; the thing itself — the enjoyment, the happiness — they do indeed profess to pursue ; but called by its own name — its proper, its essential name — they run away from it, they refuse to grasp it; any nonsense, any confusion, rather than the name of pleasure. It may be said that Hume does not employ the word virtue as the genus generalissimum, and that thence his discernment is not impli cated by the fact that some of his virtues have, in reality, no virtue in them. But if virtue do not mean something that is useful, or productive of that which is useful for the increase of well-being, what does it mean ? What is its value? In the very constitution of virtue, it must be admitted there is evil— some suffering, some self-denial, some sacrifice of good, and conse quent uneasiness — but as the practice of virtue HUME'S VIRTUES. 225 grows into a habit, the uneasiness becomes less and less, and at last may vanish altogether, (Virtue is a moral quality, in contradistinction to an intellectual quality: it belongs to the will — to the affections — not to the understand ing, except in as far as the understanding acts upon the volition. And this premised, a correct estimate of Hume's desirable qualities may be much assisted by distinguishing and grouping them under the following heads : — First. Qualities not belonging to the will, but to the understanding, such as discretion, order, quickness of conception. Second. Qualities of the will, the quality being neither a virtue nor a vice exclusively, but either a virtue or a vice, or neutral, accord ing to the object towards which it is directed, as sociability, secrecy, constancy, mercy, gene rosity. Third. Qualities which are always virtues, and consequently belonging to one of the two classes, prudence or benevolence. Fourthly. Qualities which are always virtues • — modifications of, or subordinate to the two primary classes — such as honesty, justice. Now it is really only in the third and fourth classes that the virtues, the undoubted virtues, are to be found. Qualities there are, in the first and second class, which, when associated VOL. T. Q 226 DEONTOLOGY. with prudence and benevolence, may be highly important auxiliaries. That tact, for example, which has the gift of following actions to their consequences, and which is sometimes called the virtue of discretion, how invaluable may not its co-operation be in the moral field ? So the alliance of a sociable spirit with prudence and benevolence, naturally gives to each of them an attraction which must add to their beneficial influences; but, at the same time, who fails to see that the quality called discretion depends much on mental organization, — that no efforts will introduce into an inferior mind a quantity of it equal to that which directs a superior mind ? While, again, the quality which is called sociability, far from being a co-adjutor of virtue, may be, and frequently is, the companion of vice — aye, and sometimes the very instrument by which vice accomplishes her most fatal triumphs. Though Hume has brought forward his vir tues in a strangely disassociated and disjointed state, it will be, perhaps, most convenient to take them in the disorder in which he leaves them. No classification of them will make what is not virtue, virtue ; and such virtue as is really in them will be found marshalled under the appropriate heads to which the virtue belongs. HUME'S VIRTUES. 227 Sociability. It is a disposition to seek the society of others. It is good or bad, virtuous or vicious, according to the purpose and the con duct of the social man. It has only so much of virtue in it as it has of benevolence, and if it be combined with benevolence, it becomes friendliness — friendliness, which stands in Hume's list as a distinct virtue. A disposition to avoid maleficence is generally a concomitant part of the social character, and thus far it is in accordance with the laws of negative effective benevolence. But sociability may be accom panied, and is so not unfrequently, particularly where exercised towards persons of different conditions, with tyranny or maleficence ; often it has wit for one of its instruments, wit of a pain-giving or pleasure-destroying character. Sociability may be used for the purposes of insolence, of which many examples are to be found in the writings of Cicero,* It may ally itself with scorn, as it did in the case of Burke ; so that a man, hunting over the field of socia bility for morality or happiness, may find neither. Sociability then, standing alone, says nothing for good or evil. It may represent self-regard **' I was not thirteen/ said Mr Bentham, on one occa sion, to the writer, ( when the abominations of Cicero shocked me.* 228 DEONTOLOGV. in an offensive shape, and become an instru ment of self-eulogium for evil-producing qua lities. It may be the associate of fraud and rapine, and lend the fascinations of its presence to every project of folly and vice and crime. Good-nature. It is nearly allied with socia bility, but is, with reference to virtue and vice, completely ambiguous. So much of it as is natural, or part of the distinctive individual character, cannot be deemed a virtue. That portion of it which is acquired, which is the result of reflection, supposing it can be distin guished and separated from the rest, may be virtuous. , Associated with benevolence, it is, like sociability, nearly synonymous with friend liness. It has in it a greater mixture than soci ability of the natural with the moral character. If wholly constitutional, it is no more a virtue than beauty or strength is a virtue; it adds agreeableness to social intercourse, whether conduct be virtuous or not. That part of good nature which, independently of physical ten dencies, has become effective benevolence, that, and that alone, is virtue; but it is not the good- nature that is the virtue, it is the effective benevolence. So, again, good-nature may lend itself to the service of imprudence or improbity. The disposition to please another has not un- frequently been the cause of misconduct. Even HUME'S VIRTUES. 229 in common parlance, a man is sometimes said to have been led astray by his good-nature. It may be the weakness upon which temptation acts ; and the pleasure of gratifying the person who appeals to it may close the eyes to the consequences of every consequent evil. Humanity. It is effective benevolence, or a disposition towards effective benevolence, spe cifically directed to a particular case of suffer ing. Its object is the removal of some positive and weighty evil. It is very like good-nature under excitement. It implies the exercise of not inconsiderable power of relief on the part of the humane man, and, for the most part, sup poses that, but for the exercise of his humanity, the relieved object will be subjected to greater evils than those humanity seeks to remove. But to this there are some exceptions; the hu manity of a king would lead him to pardon at the expense of penal justice ; the consequence of which would be good on a small scale, and evil on a large one: the balance being a great public loss ; and the exercise of humanity not a virtue, but a vice. It may therefore be, or may not be, praiseworthy. Its title to the name of virtue can only be judged of when the pains it removes are weighed against the pains it creates. It is apt to commit errors under present impulses. Where, for example, the 230 DEONTOLOGY. discipline or punishment attending imprudence is likely to correct that imprudence, and huma nity steps in to ward off that punishment, so that the imprudence will be repeated in con sequence of being unvisited by punishment, the humanity, far from being a virtue, is really a vice. And such cases are of frequent occur rence, ' IVJany of our institutions, called humane and charitable, whose object is to screen mis conduct from its penalties, do, in fact, only minister to human misery. Indiscriminate alms giving may, in the same way, be a premium to idleness and profligacy. It is pernicious wherever it weakens the moral sanction to such an extent as to produce, by the deterioration of character, a quantity of future pain, greater than that which it immediately removes. The lesson to be taught humanity, in order to make it virtuous, is that of calculation. Its disposi tion is always to remove a pain, and to forget the salutary influence of that pain upon the time to come. It is only, therefore, as con nected with prudence and benevolence that humanity is entitled to approval. Mercy. It is humanity; but it supposes the object of it to be more directly dependent on him who exercises it. The party served is here in the hands of the party serving; their mutual position more contrasted by the help- HUME'S VIRTUES. 231 lessness of the one party and the power of the other. To form a right judgment of the cased in which mercy may be exercised with a view to the greatest happiness principle, depends on the intellectual part of man ; the disposition to its exercise, on his moral' part. Attached to it are ideas of power, associated with vague conceptions of tyranny. These grow out of the distance between the dispenser and the reci pient of mercy. In the political field, the law which has been laid down in the case of huma nity applies here. The mercy — the favor to the individual — must be weighed against the evil done to the community. The demand made upon mercy is usually greater than that made upon humanity. Its value, in the esti mate of virtue, must be calculated by its effects. The portion of it which has virtue in it belongs to effective benevolence. Gratitude is effective benevolence, in act or disposition, in consideration of services re ceived by the grateful person, or some person connected with him by the ties of sympathy, Its efficiency is not a necessary consequence of its existence; it may be a state of mind remaining inoperative for want of occasion. It grows in the mind of the grateful person, out of benefits conferred on him. But it is not necessarily virtuous ; for virtue, doing a small 232 DEONTOLOGY. quantity of good, may be accompanied by vice, doing a large quantity of mischief. A man has conferred on me a service. He is in prison for a^ flagitious crime. To rescue him would be gratitude, but it would not be virtue. Gratitude is a subject of great laudation. Every body is fond of gratitude, because every bocfy who does a favor likes to receive favors in return. Yet effective benevolence may be more efficient where no gratitude has place. Gratitude is a most popular virtue ; it is fed by self-regard : and ingratitude is represented as a very hideous vice. All men are interested in endeavoring to obtain repayment for benefits lent. And the public-opinion tribunal has affixed a special stigma upon him who, upon occasion, does not make the return of services he has received. He who does a benefit is supported by the concurrence of society in anticipating the fruits of gratitude, or a benefit in exchange. And every man has greater ex pectation of good services from an acquaintance than from a stranger. A refusal 6f services from an acquaintance, and especially from one you have obliged, produces more annoyance than the refusal of services by a person unknown to you. In fine, gratitude, in so far as it is under the guidance of utility, may be ranked among the HUME'S VIRTUES. 233 virtues, but it may be so counterbalanced by evil as to belong to the regions of vice. Opposed to gratitude is ingratitude, of which resentment is one of the forms. Gratitude pro duces good deeds, and resentment evil deeds. Resentment may be used in an ambi-lateral sense ; a man may resent a kindness as well as an unkindness. Resentment in action is maleficence. It was the sign of a certain degree of advance ment in morality, to think of making ingratitude a crime : but it was the sign of an era but little advanced in wisdom, not to see that it was impracticable to designate it as a crime on all occasions. How long and intricate an account must it not often be necessary to take between two persons who have lived much together, before it can be known, in point of good offices, which of them is the debtor ? The fortunes, the necessities of each must be known. The most generous, the most worthy, would stand always the worst chance. The most crafty, the least sincere, would be sure to gain the cause. What he gave he would give before witnesses; what he received he would receive in secret : there would soon be no such thing as either generosity on the one hand, or gratitude on the other. 234 DEONTOLOGY. Friendliness is effective benevolence on a small scale. Like good-nature, it is a disposition to confer benefits ; but the disposition is principally directed towards those with whom the friendly person has had intercourse. It is ready to act whenever the opportunity may present itself. It imports somewhat more than a disposition to acts of kindness, and is accompanied by sympathy in a state of considerable activity. The notion of friendliness involves with it that of sympathy, at least in the common relations of life. In some of the higher walks, parti cularly the political, though the language of friendship is used, the sentiment is hardly sup posed to exist. Its connection with effective benevolence is, as has been stated, intimate; it is also sometimes produced by the self- regarding affections. To the two branches of morality, all in it that constitutes virtue must be referred. Its good and its evil may be considerably modified by the application of right principles to its operation, which, in fact, is the only reason for its admission into the field of inquiry. Morals are not made for application to that which is unchangeable, but to that which may be modified or changed by a more correct view of things. Aristotle has made friendship a sort of cousin to the virtues. It is a state or condition of life HUME'S VIRTUES. 235 constituted by a certain sort of relation analo gous to maritality, uxoriality, paternity, ma ternity, filiality. It is a species of marriage, without sexual communion for its bond, or pro geny for its consequence, and is thence not for life or for a specific term. Generosity, where a virtue, is effective bene volence, — friendliness on a larger scale; it is friendliness not bounded by the circle of ac quaintance, but extending to persons in general. Friendliness implies a preference. Generosity is diffusive. Generosity, without the guidance of prudence or benevolence, is vice and folly. He who gives away all that he has to another, who wants it less than himself, and thus confers less pleasure than he sacrifices, does a very gene rous, but a very foolish act. So he who lavishes money, or money's worth, for a pernicious pur pose, however generous the expenditure, is doing a vicious deed. The benevolence must be judged of by the sacrifice made. A small sum of money, for example, given by a poor man, would be evi dence of generosity ; while the giving a consi derable sum would scarcely be so from a man extremely opulent. The, generosity of the poor is generally visible in personal services, in the dedication of their time, in the exposure of their 236 DEONTOLOGY. persons, in the risks they run. That of the more privileged classes in a mixture of personal and pecuniary services. As the value of money becomes less, and the station of the generous person is higher, money becomes more and more the instrument of generosity. At every stage, however, the same tests apply. Beneficence, it has been already remarked, is not necessarily a virtue. To render services, to do good to others, is not always a virtuous act. Every man who spends money is bene- / ficent, a doer of good ; but there is no virtue m) doing so. To discharge the common functions of nature is beneficent ; to eat and drink, to sleep, to dress, anything by which good is done. Where beneficence differs from effective bene volence, though it may be a good, it is not a virtue. The distinction has been so frequently drawn in the course of this work, that it is needless to repeat it here. Justice is effective benevolence, wherever it deserves the credit of virtue. It is the rendering of services where they are expected, on ade quate grounds. It is the doing good where disappointment would attach to its not being done, and the public-opinion tribunal sanctions the expectation that it will be done, ^ In civil matters and in penal matters justice is a very different thing. In the social field, HUME'S VIRTUES. 237 justice is that which secures a man from the disappointment which would deprive him of objects to which he has a right, recognized by society. It is the application of the disappoint ment-preventing principle. If it is not this, it is what any person chooses to call justice. The law, * Do unto another as you would he should do unto you/ does not apply here, nor would it serve as a definition of justice, because no one would willingly inflict punishment on himself, and the infliction of punishment is often neces sary to establish the claims of justice. Justice in penal matters is the application of penal remedies. The best justice is the best application of remedies against the evils of maleficence. It has only to do with acts, and not with dispositions. The dispositions belong to the moral, the acts to the political field. In the class consisting of eleven qualities useful to ourselves, there is a jumble of qua lities almost identical, though called by different names. It would be difficult to distinguish in what respect, as to virtue, discretion and caution differ from prudence, honesty and fidelity from justice; how economy and frugality are to be disassociated from prudence ; why industry and assiduity are disunited ? But a few words upon each may serve to remove some of the mists which are gathered round the temple of morality. 238 DEONTOLOGY. Discretion is the right judgment formed for the purpose of action, in cases of more or less difficulty. It is the quality of mind which makes for itself a correct estimate of probable results. It is the forethought which marks out the most appropriate line of proceeding in a given course. It is intellectual aptitude directed to conduct. But this is no more a virtue than the power of solving an arithmetical problem is a virtue, or than the possession of animal strength is a virtue. It is cleverness, derived either from birth or from education. Industry is an ambiguous word; supposing labor applied to purposes not illaudable, it includes activity with a view to profit. It may be an instrument in the hands of other virtues ; it is no virtue of itself. In another language, if not in our own, the word is sometimes em ployed in an unfavorable sense, chevalier d1 In dustrie meaning a swindler or cheat, the expres sion implying that diligence is used in furthering the purposes of fraud. Frugality imports action positive or negative. It is prudence employed in the pecuniary field ; self-regarding prudence, for the most part. It is the check which prevents from being wasted or needlessly diminished, those pleasures which are purchaseable by wealth. It is adjacent,, as Hume remarks, to two vices— to prodigality, HUME'S VIRTUES. 239 which is imprudence; to avarice, which is op posed to effective benevolence. Honesty is subordinate to justice. It is some times an ambiguous phrase. Montaigne says every body ought to be honest in talking of his own virtues. He forgets that such talk will be likely to wound the self-love of another. A man may to himself prefer himself, but such self-preference is not very likely to be recog nized by a second person. Fidelity is also subordinate to justice. It is the manifestation of an active faculty, and im plies the observance of a contract, specific or understood. Truth is not a human quality — is not a virtue. Veracity is a far more convenient word ; and veracity is a virtue which occupies a very inap propriate place in the public mind, and the breaches of which are in consequence protected, to a great extent, by the popular sanction. Thucydides says, that in his time one hero would ask another, ( Are you a robber?' The days are come in which a man might ask another, ' Are you an advocate ? ' — an advocate being one whose power is in his tongue, and who sells that power to the first comer — to the right side or the wrong side, as may be ; to advocate * justice or to defeat justice. {JThe old days were days of force ; the present are days of fraud. 240 DEONTOLOGY. The powers of the body had once the mastery, now those of the mind. It was physical force that then ruled, — it is now mental fraud. Lying has to a great extent introduced itself into the daily forms of society ; useless always, and frequently pernicious. It may not on every occasion do harm to others, but it invariably does harm to the liar himself. It will inevita bly lower him in the opinion of others, unless, as in the case of some of the professions, he is specially endowed with the privilege of lying. The Spaniard who says, ' Esta casa es de V.' ' This house is your's/ when you quit him after a visit, tells a lie to no purpose whatever. The Frenchman who says, 'Je suis enchant^ ' — 'je suisdeso!6' — 'I am enchanted' — 'I am desola ted,' — though he preserves all the while his tran- quility, lies to no purpose whatever. The Eng lishman who says ' Not at home/ though he is at home, lies to no purpose whatever. In the terms of politeness, so called, mendacity occupies a leading place. The confusion of ideas between truth and veracity has often created great ambiguities of expression. Brissot was misled by it. He wrote a book on La Vwite, which verity marched him about as if it had been a will-o'the-wisp he was running after. Sometimes it was a knowledge of things, sometimes it was veracity, correctness HUME'S VIRTUES. 241 of statement — the truth ; sometimes it was the love of truth, in resistance to religious tyranny ; by which he meant that knowledge which is the result of evidence, as opposed to those declara tions of belief which do not grow out of evi dence, but out of authority. He sometimes used it to represent the substantial fact of the real existence of certain objects. In fact, truth in the abstract, and with the vague associations which attach to it, is a very strange entity, and slippery as an eel. Veracity is the disposition of a man to give to others the exact impression of his own mind; it is the avoidance of misrepresentation, and that growing out of attention, intense in proportion to the importance of the representation itself. Veracity being wholly subordinate to pru dence and benevolence, is its exercise a virtue in a case where neither would be violated by its infraction, or would such infraction be a vice ? No ! but to find such cases would be no easy task. Veracity is not indeed of any value but with a reference to the circumstances that surround it. In the case of lying, it may be seen how insufficient the often employed religious sanction is for restraining childhood from vice. A child has it said to him, 'If you tell a lie you will go to hell;' he tells a lie, the menaced pu- VOL. i. R 242 DEONTOLOGY. nishment does not fall upon him, and the menace soon ceases to have any influence. If the child believe, his next thoughts may naturally be — ' I may as well tell a hundred lies, it will not make the matter worse.' Sincerity has a wider import than veracity. It js a breach of sincerity not to state a fact ; it is no breach of veracity. There is much less scruple in not stating things than in stating things falsely ; it is the contrast between what is negative and what is positive. To state what is annoying to another when no purpose is answered of corresponding pleasure, chance of pleasure, or exemption from pain, is the con trary of virtuous. Where there is a solemn demand for truth, the cases are few where it should not be disclosed. The importance of veracity must also be con sidered with a reference to the number of per sons interested in it. He who deceives two commits a greater crime than he who deceives one. Falsehoods are susceptible of a classifica tion which will serve to point out .the extent of their mischievousness and consequent immoral ity. Malicious falsehoods are flagitious ; they should be avoided for the sake of others. Inter ested falsehoods are mean ; a man should avoid them for his own sake. So falsehoods to excite HUME'S VIRTUES. 243 astonishment are to a certain extent interested falsehoods, which for his own sake a. man should avoid. Falsehoods of humanity, falsehoods to avoid hurting the self-love of others or exposing the persons or property of others to injury ; as where, for instance, an assassin is in pursuit of his intended victim, and is misled by a falsehood told him as to the direction taken by the person he is pursuing ; these may be innocent and benevolent, as long as they do not give cause to suspect a general indifference to veracity. If lavishly employed this will infallibly be the result ; thence the demand of prudence that their employment should be most rare, as in fact the demand for them is rare. Falsehoods of necessity; such as are and must be used to madmen ; falsehoods of self- defence, against lawless violence, come under the same conditions. Equivocation differs from falsehood, and is preferable to it, inasmuch as it gives the chance that if the equivocator cannot immediately dis cover terms sufficiently ambiguous for equivo cation, he will tell the truth. An equivocation is a falsehood in ideas, not in words. A lie is a falsehood both in ideas and words. The having recourse rather to equivocation 244 DEONTOLOGY. than to a lie direct, shows a certain regard to truth ; for though an equivocation might be pre ferred to truth, truth may be preferred to a lie. Truth may be had from a person who deals in equivocations ; for he may be taken on a sudden, before he has time to put together an equivocation. If a man is known only for an equivocator, it is also known that there is a method of dealing with him. It is to press him with distinctions upon the terms of his answers, till you get him to terms not susceptible of ambiguity. You by this means force him at last to take his chance between simple truth and downright false hood. An equivocator gives evidence of a disposition to keep upon terms with truth. Perjury is lying in the case where the reli gious sanction is put prominently forward as the guarantee for truth and the check upon falsehood. The force of the religious sanction depends wholly upon the state of the mind of the indi vidual to whom it is applied. It will add nothing to the power of eliciting truth in cases where the popular sanction is in full activity. In the cases of oaths and vows the sanction is the same. The profanation of a vow diminishes the force of the sanction as applied to promises of future conduct ; it therefore diminishes the force HUME'S VIRTUES. 245 of the same sanction as applied to relations of past conduct or past events. There are cases where a vow, though an under taking for future conduct, may be violated in the act of taking it. Such is that of a vow taken to believe a proposition, of the truth of which the person vowing has no conviction at the time. The guilty of this profanation are those who insist on this sacrifice of principles to prejudices, on pretence of securing a tranquillity of mind which would be far better compassed by that liberty which takes away the motives to debate. As a means of this tranquillity their own voice is in favour of these forced professions ; the voice of experience in every country where this liberty is perfect, and of every country in which it has been admitted at all, as far as it has been admitted, is against them. Among the Romans, while the undertaking was confined to respect things at once useful and practicable, such as obedience to the order of a general, the force of this sanction was stupendous. Veracity and mendacity are less immediately connected than the other virtues with pleasure and pain. Hence the difficulty of assigning to their modifications the character that belongs to them. Sincerity and insincerity, ingenuous- 246 . DEONTOLOGY. ness and disingenuousness, are more or less pernicious, more or less virtuous or vicious, as the particular case may exhibit them. Silence itself may have all the mischief and culpability of mendacity, where, for instance, the convey ance of information is a matter of duty, where prudence or benevolence require that the infor mation should be given. Veracity, in some cases, demands fortitude for an ally, and forti tude becomes a virtue when the alliance is to further the ends of sound morality. Caution is near akin to discretion, but has i more timidity in it, and is applied to subjects from whence greater danger may arise. It is prudence wherever there is virtue in it. Enterprize is activity, combined with com parative fearlessness with reference to evil re sults ; it is one of the forms of activity, and may be considered a species of intellectual courage, either facing danger (i. e. probable evil) or turning aside from it. This may be either the result of the will, or of the non- application of the will to the subject. Attention is the applicaction of the will, when the will is acted on with a considerable degree of force. Assiduity is a continued enterprize, applied for a considerable length of time to the same subject, without any long interruption. Economy is frugality combined with good HUME'S VIRTUES. 247 management, which is an intellectual attribute ; it is sometimes used without reference to eco nomy, and implies a self-denial which is not necessary to economy. Temptations to dissi pation surround every man; and here, as on other parts of the field, the continued practice of self-denial is a habit of virtue. Follow a list of qualities, fourteen in number, of which Hume says nobody can for a moment refuse them the tribute of praise and appro bation. Of these temperance, sobriety, and pa tience are but emanations from self-regarding prudence. Constancy, perseverance, forethought, and consider ateness, when virtues, are modifica tions of prudence, but are not necessarily vir tues, — nay, they may be vices. Secrecy, when a virtue, belongs to prudence or effective bene volence; while order, insinuation, address, presence of mind, quickness of conception, and facility of expression, are, for the most part, intellectual attributes, and in no wise entitled to be clas sified either as virtues or vices, except in as far as they are regulated by the will. Sobriety is temperance applied to any thing producing intoxication. Patience may refer either to sensation or to action; it is the non-indication of suffering equal to the actual suffering, and the more 248 DEONTOLOGY. patient a man is, the less is his suffering in creased by duration. Constancy has many meanings; constancy, in a bad cause, would be vice, as, in a good cause, it is virtue : it is perseverance in a cause, whether right or wrong; it is perseverance, in spite of temptation. It is vicious, virtuous, or neuter. A man constantly eats, drinks, and sleeps ; but his eating, drinking, and sleeping are not acts of vice nor virtue. Perseverance rather imports continuity of action : like constancy, it may, or may not, be virtue. It calls attention into exercise. Forethought is imagination applied to future contingent events : it is necessary to the proper exercise of self-regarding prudence. Its value depends on the remoteness and complexity of the objects towards which it is directed, Considerateness is the bringing together toll the ideas that bear on a subject with reference to the end in view; the end constituting the merit or demerit of the quality, Secrecy is a negative quality. It is negative effective benevolence, applied to the case where the disclosure of facts would be prejudicial to others ; it is self-regarding prudence when the disclosure would be prejudicial to the individual himself. When a secret is committed to you, HUME'S VIRTUES. 249 and the divulging it would do no harm to your self or others, the divulging it is a breach of contract. Order is a modification of method ; it is the putting things one after another, so that some particular end is answered by the arrangement. Order is an abstract word, which you cannot do without any more than you can do without the word time: it is the placing things in a line; it is a compound non-entity, growing out of our ideas of space and time. Insinuation is the faculty of recommending oneself to another by action or discourse, ac companied by a desire that the faculty should not be detected. It is the art of ingratiation — the making oneself an object of sympathy, with a concealment of the purpose. Address is an instrument of insinuation ; it is insinuation in a wider field of thought and action. Presence of mind is a power over one's own mind ; it is the faculty of readily bringing into view all the several considerations necessary to correct decision : it is that which takes prompt measures for the prevention of evil. Quickness of conception should have preceded ' presence of mind.' It is a simple idea ; it is implied in the idea of presence of mind. 250 DEONTOLOGY^ Facility of expression can be no virtue; it is quickness of conception giving language to its thought. The qualities agreeable to ourselves are, according to Hume, cheerfulness, dignity or magnanimity, courage and tranquillity. Cheerfulness, in so far as it is a natural disposition, is not a virtue : in so far as it is acquired, it is prudence. It is the being pleased, and the giving expression to the sense of plea- sure. It is, to a very great extent, an endow ment of a particular constitutional temperament. Virtue is something which can be excited by effort; it is something which obeys our com mands : but a disposition to sadness, or a dis position to gladness, does not obey our com mands. By study we may diminish the one and increase the other, and by so doing we give evidence of, and exercise to, self-regarding prudence. By far the larger portion of cheerful ness is inherent, though enjoyment acts upon it, and tends greatly to its increase. ' The habit of doing good/ as benevolence has been called, is the best instructor how to make instruments of cheerfulness. Every being who is the recipi ent of benevolence may be a source of future pleasure, and of exemption from future pain. Dignity, when a virtue, is extra-regarding HUME'S VIRTUES, 251 prudence; it may be exhibited in behavior, or it may ;be the exhibition alone of the instru ments of dignity. Courage may be a virtue or may be a vice. To a great extent it is a natural quality : it does not always imply self-denial, nor always exhibit benevolence. It may be, perhaps, more properly said that courage is neither' a virtue nor a vice, but an instrument of either, its character depending wholly on its application. For a man to value himself on his courage, without any reference to the occasions on which it is exercised, is to value himself on a quality possessed in a far higher degree by a dog, especially if the dog is mad. Tranquillity is insensibility to external causes of suffering, and particularly of remote suffering. Every man desires to keep in view objects that are agreeable, and out of view objects that are disagreeable. The qualities which Hume introduces, as agreeable to others, are politeness, wit, decency, and cleanliness. Politeness is more of a negative than a posi tive quality. It is the avoidance of actions or behavior which may be disagreeable to the person with whom you have to do. Its positive branch is the doing whatever it may be agree able to others that you should do. In all 252 • DEONTOLOGY. cases where the laws of prudence and bene volence are not opposed to the usages of society, self-interest demands attention to them. The highest order of politeness is the application of the rules which are recognized |jn^ high life. But herejthsre is mingled with it so much mendacity, and that of a useless, even when not vprominently pernicious character, that the analysis of politeness must be thoroughly made before its character can be determined-/ It easily degenerates into self-esteem, and instead of an instrument of pleasure, becomes one of annoyance. Many men intend to communicate enjoyment, — for example, by stories, by exces sive attentions, and other efforts, which are the cause of weariness to those whom they really desire to gratifyJ Fashion is the competition for admiration, and its vices begin where annoy ances are caused to others for the purposes of selfishness. In some cases, as in the courts where etiquette is carried farthest, the sacrifice of the many to the one, of the comforts of the many to the pride of the one, is striking. Under the Bourbons at the Tuileries, etiquette required that, until the King sat down to cards, every body must stand, however weary. This was politeness, this was etiquette, but it was absurdity and folly. Wit is a very ambiguous virtue. Locke says HUME'S VIRTUES. 253 that wit consists in discovering resemblances ; • judgment, in discovering differences. Wit con fers power, and is thence an object of desire : it is the power of giving pleasure to some, but often at the expense of pain to others. If the subject of malevolent wit is present, his pain is immediate ; if absent, he suffers from losing a portion of the good opinion of others, and the quantity of his suffering cannot be traced. One of the merits of wit is that it should be unexpected. There is a species of it which may be produced from a dictionary by the mere juxta-position of words. Quidlibet cum quod- libet may be applied to its production. Wit has no existence except where the ana logy elicited is brought to view ; it may be by contrast, but the analogy or the contrast should be suddenly produced. Decency is a term vague and unsatisfactory. It means, as generally used, the avoidance of bringing forward what is disagreeable to others. This is a negative virtue. When it comes in a positive shape, it is frequently only an eccle siastical virtue, employing wealth for the pur poses of delusion. Decency is to cover the throne with crimson, to carve the pulpit, to provide lawn sleeves; it is to do that which it is agreeable to the ruling few to have done. Delicacy is one of the branches of decency, but 254 DEONTOLOGY. more commonly referring to the avoidance of physical annoyances. It is not an unusual thing for men to take merit to themselves for being disgusted with that which does not dis gust people in general, and to imagine that this affected sensibility is a mark of their belonging to the aristocratic classes. Decorum is another of the forms of decency ; it refers, for the most part, to the avoidance of matters of small mo ment, the non-avoidance of which would expose us to the contempt of others. Cleanliness acts through the medium of the imagination ; it is a negative virtue. It is the avoidance of practices by which disease, or the apprehension of disease, is produced. The neglect of salutary attentions to the person is im mediately associated with the idea of disease. Dirt, for example, left on the body, calls up the thought of unhealthiness. It is a sort of mislocation of matter in small particles; and attention to cleanliness is demanded by pru dence, in as far as inattention to it is injurious to ourselves ; by benevolence, in as far as inat tention to it is offensive to others. The im pression of its absence may be produced where the intrusive substances are not in themselves disagreeable. Gold-dust sticking to a man's face would give nearly the same impression of a want of cleanliness as any other substance, just HUME'S VIRTUES. 255 as the finest white powder on a scuttle of coals would give a notion of impurity. And Hume concludes his list by the intro duction of two virtues, classified as good qua lities in society. They are chastity and alle giance. Chastity is the refraining from sensual enjoyments where indulgence is improper, where their gratification would be productive of more pain to others than of pleasure to him who indulges in them. Modesty is not neces sarily a branch of chastity. There may be constant unchastity without immodesty. Gross language — language in the highest degree immo dest, may be unaccompanied with an unchaste act; and acts of unchastity may be indulged in, without the utterance of an immodest word. Allegiance is vagueness itself, unless the spe cial subject be shewn, and then it is effective benevolence on the largest scale, provided the object of allegiance is conformable to the greatest happiness principle. All depends on the cha racter of that government for which allegiance is claimed. .Allegiance may be an obvious virtue, it may be a very pernicious crime. A good government is that in which the influence is placed in the hands of those who are inte rested in the exercise of benevolent power. Allegiance is a term employed instead of obe dience. Obedience is good when the govern- 256 DEONTOLOGY. ment is good, — bad when the government is bad. Opposition to institutions friendly to human happiness is vice proportioned to the amount of their excellence. Opposition to institutions unfriendly to human happiness is virtue pro portioned to the amount of their mischief. So far, at least, is the teaching of effective bene volence ; but if the sacrifice made to overthrow bad governments exceeds the chances of good to be produced by their overthrow, then virtue demands abstention. No case can be conceived in which virtue will allow the dictates of self- regarding interest to attempt the overthrow of good institutions ; for the amount of evil with which others would be visited must com pletely absorb the amount of good which the individual could obtain for himself. The examples given by Hume are, for the most part, mere assumptions that he, the mo ralist, is to decide on all the cases that come before him.Y He occupies a pulpit whence he deals out his moral dogmas, and speaks as if he were the representative of higher virtues than the man to whom he is speaking./ When he gives no examples, it is mere idle trum- petting, tantarara and fiddle-de-dee. He draws no intelligible distinctions between pleasure, passion, and pain : he makes distinctions where there are no differences, and dreams of settling HUME'S VIRTUES. 257 moral points by phrases, such as * It is becom ing/ which are the mere sic volo despotism of an instructor. ^Pleasure and pain are the only clues for unravelling the mysteries of morality. Fly where you will, fumble about as you please, no other master key shall you find, to open all the doors which lead into the temple oftruth.*^ How does it happen that so many vague words, with vague ideas, or no ideas at all attached to them, have so long kept possession of the field ? It is because we imagine we thoroughly comprehend the terms which are familiar to us. What we are continually talking of, merely from our having been continually talking of it, we imagine we understand. So close an union has habit cemented between words and things, that we take one for the other, and when we have words in our ears we imagine we have thoughts in our minds. When an unusual * The services of Hume, in many parts of the field of moral and mental philosophy, were immense. He first drew a clear distinction between impressions and ideas, a distinc tion, without which it is hardly possible to obtain any clear notions on many topics of leading importance. The dis tinction is obvious when pointed out: — I see a man — it is a. perception : I close my eyes, but imagine myself to see him still — it is an idea. VOL. I. S 258 DEONTOLOGY. word presents itself, we challenge it ; we exa mine ourselves, to see whether we have an idea annexed to it ; but when a word that we are familiar with comes across us, we let it pass on, under favor of old recognition. The long acquaintance we have had with it makes us take for granted we have investigated all its meaning; we deal by it, in consequence, as the Custom-house officers in certain coun tries, who, having once set their seal upon a packet, so long as they see, or think they see their seal upon it, reasonably enough suppose themselves dispensed with • from visiting and examining the contents of it anew. FALSE VIRTUES, 259 CHAPTER XVII. FALSE VIRTUES. THERE are other qualities which have been put forward by different writers on morality as virtues, and as entitled to the praise and the recompense of virtue. In most cases they are of ambiguous character, and as they present certain points of contact with prudence and benevolence, they obtain the character of vir tue, not so much on account of their essential attributes as of their accidental association with qualities really virtuous. The very defect of character may in this way be made to present an aspect of virtue : and the affections may be so engaged with one side of a question, as to interfere with a right judgment of its moral merit, A mother steals a loaf to satisfy the hunger of a starving child. How easy it would be to excite the sympathies in favor of her maternal tenderness, so as to bury all con sideration of her dishonesty in the depth of those sympathies. And, in truth, nothing but an enlarged and expansive estimate, such as would take the case out of the regions of sen- 260 DEONTOLOGY. timentality into the wider regions of public good, could ever lead to the formation of a right judgment in such matters. Contempt for Riches. Socrates' contempt for riches was mere affectation and pride, just as meritorious as it would have been for him to have remained standing for a long time on one leg. It was only denying to himself the doing the good which riches would have enabled him to do. The desire of wealth is the desire, in a vague form, to possess what wealth can obtain. So again, his denying himself assist^ ance from others was a mere self-regarding calculation, it was only to excite their self- esteem for other purposes ; it was a calculation to receive more than he would otherwise obtain — it was a refusal of 100/. in order to get 200/. So Epictetus, — he had more pleasure in pride than in benevolence. He paid himself out of the testimonies of respect with which he was surrounded. He calculated on getting more from self-denial than he could get without it. But he was less meritorious than the Oriental fakirs, who suffer more than he. His conduct was that of the miser who stores his wealth, that, on any future occasion, he may command what he pleases by the exercise of that instru ment of power. He pays himself with the FALSE VIRTUES. 261 pleasures of imagination, which are greater to him than those of actual fruition. Misers, as they grow older, have less sense of present enjoyment, and become, therefore, more and more disposed to avarice, which is an anticipa tion of a future reward. Love of Action. Love of action, without an object, is nothing : it has in it neither vice nor virtue. Such part of it as proceeds from the will, and is directed to the production of hap piness, is virtuous. Such part as is intellectual is neutral; where it is the act of the will, and is directed to the production of evil, it is vicious. Attention. It is the quality which distin guishes the botanist who carefully gathers the flower, from the clown who tramples it under his feet. Fixed attention has been lately brought forward as a virtue, and a pretty virtue it is ; so that if I purpose to murder a man, and fix my attention upon it, that is a virtue ! Enterprize has also been honoured with the title of virtue. Enterprize, which may be as bad a vice as any in the calendar. And dispatch has reached the same laudatory eleva tion.* Dispatch is the employment of the least quantity of time sufficient for the attain- * Most of the above are introduced as virtues by Jevons, in his Principles of Morality. 262 DEONTOLOGY. meot of an object. It is quickness without precipitation. It is a prudent means, which may be used for an end either of good or evil. But, having established a general rule, which every one may apply for himself to the estimate of those qualities of which he desires to form a judgment, — having shown that unless they can be qlassed under the heads of prudence and effective benevolence, they are not virtues, — that only such parts of them are virtues as can be so classed, — it is scarcely needful to pursue the subject farther. THE PASSIONS. .263 CHAPTER XVIII. < THE PASSIONS. PASSION is intense emotion — emotion is evanes cent passion. The nature of the passions can only be un derstood by their division into the different heads of pleasure and pain : for the principles by which they are to be governed, reference must be made to the list of virtues and vices. Let the passion of anger be analysed, and its consequences traced. When under its influ ence, a man is suffering pain — pain produced by the contemplation of the act which has excited the passion. An immediate consequence is, a desire to produce pain in the breast of the party who has awakened the anger. Anger, then, has in it two constant ingredients — pain suffered by the angry man, and a desire to give pain to the person by whom he has been made angry. And now to the question of virtue and vice. As there is no anger without pain, the man who draws pain upon himself without the compen sation of a more lhan equivalent pleasure, vio lates the law of prudence. Next comes the desire to produce pain in the 264 DEONTOLOGY. breast of the object of anger. This desire can not be gratified without malevolence and male ficence. Here is an obvious violation of the law of benevolence. And here we have an ex emplification of the relationship between passion and pain and pleasure ; between passion and virtue and vice. Cannot anger then be indulged without vice in both its shapes, without imprudence, and without maleficence ? It cannot ! It cannot, at least, whenever it rises to the height of passion. And here a more remote, but more mischievous result presents itself to view, as a violation of the law of self- regarding prudence. The passion cannot be gratified but by the production of pain in his breast by whom the anger has been excited, and pain cannot be produced there without a counter-desire to retaliate the pain, or greater pain on him who has produced it. To the pain in the breast of the angry man there is a termi nation, and most commonly a speedy termina tion, but to the remote pain, which may be con sidered the third link in the chain of causes and effects, who can put a limit ? Anger may have had what is called its revenge, but the exercise of that revenge may have created the durable passion of enmity, to whose consequence it is impossible to affix a boundary. Since anger cannot exist without vice, what THE PASSIONS. 265 is to be done ? Can a man exist without anger ? Without anger can injuries be averted, can self- defence, can self-preservation be provided for? Certainly not without the production of pain to him who has inflicted the injury. But to the production of this pain anger is not ne cessary. Anger is no more necessary than to the surgeon by whom, to save suffering or life, a painful operation is performed. No anger is excited in his breast by the view of the agony he inflicts, or by the contemplation of the greater evil which would follow but for his in terference. That anger should never have place is not possible; it is not consistent with the structure of the human mind. But it may be said, and that on every occasion, and without any exception, that the less there is of it the better : for whatever pain is needful to the pro duction of the useful effect, that pain will be much better measured without the passion, than by it. But, it may be said, there are circumstances in which not only pain — the natural effect of anger — pain purposely produced, but anger itself, the passion of anger, is useful, and even necessary to the existence of society, and that these circumstances in our own country, ex tend over the whole field of penal jurispru dence. I have been robbed. The offender, 266 DEONTOLOGY. on conviction, will be capitally punished, or transported in a state of servitude. Shall I prosecute him ? Not if self- regarding prudence is alone to be my counsellor ; for her counsels would be — Add not to the loss inflicted by the robbery, the farther loss inflicted on you by the prosecution.. Not if I consult benevolence, for she would say, the punishment is too great for the offence. And such is the response which in the knowledge of every body, and especially when the punishment of death is menaced, fre quently determines a man's conduct. But, were the matter rightly considered, the response, it might be said, would be — Yes! prosecute ; for the good of the community re quires that neither the suffering of the offender in the shape of punishment, nor the suffering of yourself, the prosecutor, in the shape of vexa tion and expence, should be grudged. Good ! but I can ill afford it : the pecuniary burthen to me will be greater than that uncertain, unesti- mated, and remote benefit which will grow out of the prosecution and its results. Again, the responses of benevolence have no influence with me. Be they ever so decisive, they have not a preponderant weight in my mind, In this case, neither prudence nor benevolence will produce action ; and yet, if action were not produced, the security of society would suf- THE PASSIONS. 267 fer a serious shock — a shock serious in propor tion to its frequency ; and, if constant, security would be wholly destroyed, and the general ruin of property would immediately follow. The supposed virtue in both its forms, is insuffi cient to preserve society, and anger, however dissocial its character, is indispensably neces sary. It is not easy to refute this reasoning, under the present state of our penal code. But it will be immediately seen, that the necessity of the passion does not arise out of the nature of the case, and that it is produced, to a great extent, by the imperfections of our laws : for if those imperfections were removed, the demand for the passion of anger would, at all events, be very greatly diminished. Were the needless ex- pence and vexation attending a prosecution re moved, the answer of self-regarding prudence might be opposite to what it now is. Were the pernicious excess of punishment taken away, the answer of benevolence would be opposite to what it is. And if you suppose a state in which the passion of anger were subjected to the de mands of prudence and benevolence, how few would be the occasions in which the passion it self could find field for its exercise. The legislator, indeed, whose purpose is to keep delinquency within bounds, and whose 268 DEONTOLOGY. conduct is to produce effect on the national scale, has a claim upon him somewhat different from that on the individual. The self- regarding motives are, in his case, not the prominent ones, and while the inhibition of the passion in the breast of individuals seems demanded by virtue, benevolence requires from the legislator such an exercise of it as will lead to those inflictions of pain, which are likely to minimize the quantity of crime. Anger has the quality of being increased by giving vent to itself. He who swears be cause he is angry, only becomes the more angry in consequence. The appetite is increased, not satisfied, by the aliment it feeds on. What has been said of anger applies to envy and jealousy. They both imply the presence of pain. To suppress them in our own breasts is demanded by prudence ; if they exist there in an inoperative state, it is prudence alone that requires their suppression. If they are likely so to be awakened as to produce a maleficent influence upon others, their suppression is called for by benevolence. But why is reason inefficacious against passion ? It cannot raise up images lively enough. What is called reason, as applied to the government of the passions, is the making the THE PASSIONS. 269 scale turn in favor of a greater pleasure in pre ference to a less. The will necessarily yields to the solicitation of the greatest apparent good. And the causes why the influences of passion domineer over the influences of reason are— 1, Want of apparent intensity in the distant pleasure which reason promises — want of viva city in the idea of it. 2. Want of apparent certainty — want of ready discernment to trace out, at the instant, the train of effects and causes that promote or impede the production of the distant pleasure. Hence the use of the expedient, which has been frequently recommended, of playing off one passion against another. Habitually to exercise the mind in the appli cation of the true standard of morality, will be habitually to train the affections and the pas sions to virtuous tendencies and virtuous con duct. And the occasions are infinite — they are occurring every hour of our existence, nor is any occasion to be despised. Like flakes of snow that fall unperceived upon the earth, the seemingly unimportant events of life succeed one another. As the snow gathers together, so are our habits formed. No single flake that is added to the pile produces a sensible change; no single action creates, however it may exhibit, a 270 DEONTOLOGY. man's character ; but, as the tempest hurls the avalanche down the mountain, and overwhelms the inhabitant and his habitation, so passion, acting upon the elements of mischief, which pernicious habits have brought together by im perceptible accumulation, may overthrow the edifice of truth and virtue. INTELLECTUAL FACULTIES. 271 CHAPTER XIX. • INTELLECTUAL FACULTIES. BETWEEN the intellectual faculties and virtue and vice there exists an intimate relation. Wherever the will has any influence on their direction, they belong to the moral field ; and, in as far as it is in the power of the will to add. to their efficiency, they become instruments of pain and pleasure, and important in the propor tion of the amount of pain and pleasure which their exercise is able to produce. The faculty of invention, for instance, belongs to the understanding — it is intellectual ; but, whether it is an instrument in the hands of virtue or vice, depends upon its application to purposes beneficent or maleficent. But the influence of the understanding upon the will is yet more important. It is to the un derstanding that every appeal must be made, and unless it can be associated with the demands of morality, there is little prospect for the suc cess of the Deontological teacher. His reason ings, his persuasions must be addressed to the intellectual faculties. He must win them to his 272 DEONTOLOGY. side before he can influence conduct. It is by their assistance that he is to teach the arithme tic of pains and pleasures. By them he is to show what are the penalties to be paid by vice, and what are the recompenses to wait upon vir tue. He reasons ; and his reasons are prophetic of inevitable evil to imprudence and improbity ; of infallible good to prudence and benevolence. Passion appeals only to that which is, — the in tellectual faculties bring what will be into the thoughts.! They, in fact, constitute the main difference between the virtues of beasts and those of men. The lower animals, for the most part, are unchecked in their search of pleasure by any anticipation of future pain. No appre hension of consequences would lead them to abstain from any present enjoyment. Except among a few of the more intelligent, all the les sons are lost even of experience : the waste of experience being, perhaps, attributable to the imperfections of the recollecting faculty. But the mind of man stretches before and after. Reason brings events that are passed to bear upon the future. It not only draws upon expe rience, but on imagination. The field of its influence is boundless as the range of thought. Observant of consequences, it presents them to the inquirer.. It abstracts pains and pleasures from the dross that surrounds them ; it analyses INTELLECTUAL FACULTIES. 273 their value by dividing them into their compo nent parts, or gathers them up into a whole in order to ascertain the sum total. It compares them one with another when they are arranged on different sides, generalizes out of the col lected elements, and deduces the ultimate re sult. In this way do the intellectual faculties become the most important servants of virtue, leading men into the true and trust-worthy paths of felicity. Hume introduces his intellectual faculties without any arrangement or order. They may, however, be conveniently classed. First : Passive Faculties. § I — Those which operate, without need of much attention or com parison, on more than one object. 1. Perception — the source of all the other faculties. 2. Memory — becomes active when attention is applied to it. 3. Imagination — a passive quality, for it is busy even in dreams ; when active, it becomes invention. § II. Operating on two or more objects, but still without need of much attention. 1. Judgment — as in the case of vision. Second : Faculties active — volitional. § I. Operating without need of the judgment on more than one object. VOL. i. T 274 DEONTOLOGY. 1. Attention. 2. Observation — which is attention applied to a particular object. § II. — Requiring the assistance of the judg ment, and the presence of more than one object. 1. Abstraction. 2. Analysis. 3. Synthesis, or combination. 4. Comparison. 5. Generalization. 6. Deduction. § III. — Requiring the presence of two or more of the active-volitional faculties, and of two or more objects. 1. Distribution. 2. Methodization. Invention is performed by the use of the other faculties, including attention in an intense de gree, under the direction of the judgment, and having for its object the discovery of some new fact, the production of some new effort, or the formation of some new combination of ideas. Communication, with which Hume closes his list, seems to have no right to be classed among the intellectual faculties. When the intellectual faculties are not, or cannot be called into operation, conduct is taken out of the regions of virtue and vice. In INTELLECTUAL FACULTIES. 275 infancy, for example, before the mind is brought into action; in insanity, where the thinking powers are overthrown, there is no respon sibility, and, consequently, no title can be made out to praise or blame. In the case of tempo rary aberration of the reasoning powers, as under the influence of intoxication, the actor is not responsible for the act committed, while his judgment is, as it were, extinguished. It is a secondary consequence of a primary impru dence. In the case of insanity, the course to be pursued by society is clear, — the power of voluntary action must be taken away. In the case of infancy, the demand for impunity must depend on the quantity of mind which is de veloped ; and it will be found that, at a very early age, the influence of pain, which is made to visit misconduct, may be brought into operation, and from the moment that such discipline becomes operative, there is a demand for its application. In the case of acts committed under the influ ence of inebriety, there is no claim to impunity, nor can any general rule be laid down which shall be applicable to every case. All the sanc tions must be consulted, in order to exact the sufficient penalties for the past, and to obtain the most appropriate securities for the future. 270 DEONTOLOGY. CHAPTER XX. CONCLUSION. To what does all we have been advocating tend ? To the development of two principles, — first, the greatest happiness principle, or the diffusion of good, — and, secondly, the disappointment- opposing principle, or the prevention of evil. Out of these two items all the branches of mo rality grow. It may be objected, that all our reasonings have not brought our principles into the field of demonstration. What then ! If our arguments should so regulate conduct as to produce a result which will leave no regret behind it, what more have we reason to desire ? Are they strong enough to communicate that balance of pleasure towards which they tend, and to which alone they look? What better should they do ? Whether they be of that kind to which we have been accustomed to give the name of the in tuitive, or of the demonstrative, or only of the probable, it is no matter ; the satisfaction they CONCLUSION. 277 give us is perfect; and, whatever be their name, their success could be no more. Give them the name of demonstration or any other, what matters it ? It is not the name we are concerned in, but the thing. There is however something at the bottom of all this anxiety. What men want to know is, the degree of assurance they are warranted to indulge. What evidence is there that this morality is the true morality? Call the sort of proof men have of a proposi tion, demonstration, they may be positive without being exposed to accusations of rash ness either from themselves or any one else. No one can have present to his mind the proof of every proposition, how true soever, which he believes. It is for want of the thing, that men are so anxious about the word. No man, how philosophical, how scrupulous soever, but believes infinitely more propositions upon trust than upon perception : the only difference in this particular between the philo sopher and the no-philosopher, or in short be tween the wise man and the weak is, that the latter rests upon authority conclusively, in the last as well as in the first instance ; the former always keeps open the appeal to reason, that is, to his own perceptions. The judgments of the first, upon hearing the report of authority, are 278 DEONTOLOGY. provisional; the judgments of the latter are definitive. But of demonstration certain propositions are not susceptible. The proposition that happi ness is better than unhappiness cannot be sub jected to mathematical proof. But let him who impugns the doctrine impugn our reasonings. It is the only axiom we desire to have taken for granted, and this is to make a very small demand upon confidence or upon credulity. The march of utilitarian principles has been obvious. They have made their way by their native strength and excellence. How should men be better occupied than in tracing the con sequences of conduct? Observation brought with it its corresponding results. Men perceived such and such actions were useful ; they perceived such and such other actions were mischievous. They took a parti cular action, of the sort, for instance, that was mischievous : by abstracting the particular circumstances of time, of place, of parties, they formed a general idea ; to that general idea they gave a name ; that name constituted a genus to which other acts of the same nature were refer red in common. If any one took into consider ation that genus or species of action (no matter which we call it) and said of it that it was mis chievous, the proposition in which he said as CONCLUSION. 279 much, — the proposition in which he predicated mischievousness of action — formed a maxim of utility. But it is not probable that people put the quality of an action that affected them upon this conspicuous footing, in the early times of which we are speaking; those times which preceded the formation of laws. Men in gene ral are not arrived so far even now. They ex pressed their sentiments in some such obscure terms as * right ' or * fitting/ terms which served only to express their disapprobation, and not the ground of it. It is one thing (how strange soever the proposition may appear, expe rience has taught the truth of it), — it itf one thing for men to feel pain from an act, and mark that act accordingly with a sentiment of disap probation ; and another thing to fix explicitly upon that pain as the cause of that disapprobation. Nothing can be idler than the appeal to anti quity as authority. In the midst of some truths there are a thousand fallacies. The light to be found shines by contrast with surrounding darkness. Of instruments of delusion, erudition has frequently made use of the most baleful. True, such language was held, such opinions were professed by self-styled philosophers. What then? For, if from their language no practical conclusion can be drawn, — if from their 280 DEONTOLOGY. opinions no result of good can be elicited, where is their value ? Men there are whose preach ing conies to this : ' Read modern books less and ancient more. Go for the moral sciences to Aristotle, to Plato. For metaphysics, not to Locke, but still to Aris totle. For Botany, not to Linnaeus, but to Theophrastus — to ./Elian.' This is precisely the way to talk of everything and know nothing; — to be as much farther from knowledge in almost every science as a child who cannot tell his letters is from the most intelligent professor. Life is not long enough to store the mind with the facts that form the stock of the several sci ences, were no propositions presented but what are true and those dressed in their simplest garb. Yet many men would send us to rake in books in which, for ten propositions evidently false, and ten times the number of unintelligible ones, you will scarcely find a single one that is true, and that one dished out over and over again in the meanest modem compilation on the subject you can lay your hands on :) you may turn over whole vo lumes of antiquity without discovering a solitary truth to make you amends for your pains. To make this any but the most absurd (as it is one of the most pernicious.species of prejudice, the whole order of nature must be reversed. CONCLUSION. 281 The acorn must be larger than the oak it will become. A man must be wiser in his mother's womb than in the vigour of his manhood. Every thing must be supposed to grow backwards. New experiences added to the subsisting stock must lessen the number there existed before, It is scarcely possible to believe a man to stand bona fide on so noxious a system. If he do, grieve over him, but treat him as an enemy to knowledge, and to that happiness which is founded upon knowledge. The public interests demand that his notions rise not into credit. A man thinks not so highly of Plato as he deserves. What is the consequence ? Nothing. A man thinks more highly of Plato than he deserves. What is the consequence ? He goes and reads him. He tortures his brains to find meaning where there is none. He moves hea ven and earth to understand a writer who did not understand himself, and he crawls out of that mass of crudities with a spirit broken by dis appointment and humiliation. He has learned that falsehood is truth, and nonsense is sublimity. Of all the works that can be imagined, there could scarcely be a more useful one than an 'in dex expurgatorius* (but the composer of it must be a writer of sufficient eminence to give law to men's opinions) of the books which have bewil dered and betrayed mankind. 282 DEONTOLOGY. If the theory of morals which has been here developed, has in it any value, that value will be found in its simplicity, intelligibleness, and universal applicability. But let it not be sup posed, because a standard has been recom mended by which the multitudinous questions of right and wrong are measured and decided, that the discovery of this standard, and of its all- Comprehensive fitness has been unattended with laborious meditation and inquiry. The merit of deep thought consists, not in compelling the reader to descend into the profound well of truth, there to draw for himself of its healthful and refreshing waters; but in its having enabled the writer to descend and to bring up for the use of others the invigorating draught. There is little due to the man who sends another forth in search of undiscovered truth ; but he has established some claim to the good opinion of his fellow men who, having gone forth in pursuit of the treasure, brings it home and delivers it over to the keep ing of all who are willing to receive it at his hands. Of the merits of a work of which truth is the object we cannot have an adequate idea nor a perfect relish without some acquaintance with the errors against which it is levelled and which it is calculated to displace. With respect to many, the apparent merit of such a work vill CONCLUSION. 283 be apt to be in an inverse proportion to the real. The better it answers its purpose of making an abstruse subject plain, the more apt it will be to appear to have nothing in it that is extra ordinary. A single observation that seems to contain nothing more than what every body knew already, may turn volumes of specious and for midable fallacy into waste paper. The same book may succeed ill with different sorts of people for opposite reasons : by the ignorant, who have no opinion about the matter, it may be thought lightly of, as containing nothing that is extraordinary ; by the false learn ed, who have prejudices they cannot bear to have questioned, it may be condemned as para doxical, for not squaring with these prejudices. HISTORY OP THE GREATEST-HAPPINESS PRINCIPLE. HISTORY OP THE GREATEST-HAPPINESS PRINCIPLE, IF the intentions of the Author and of the Editor have been accomplished, this volume will be found to be nothing but an application of the Greatest-Happiness Principle to the field of morals. When the principle first presented itself to Mr Bentham's mind, he denominated it the Utilitarian Theory ; but he soon discovered that the phrase did not immediately present to the views of others, the ideas which he attached to it ; namely, that any thing is useful only in as far, and in as much as it promotes the hap piness of man. Happiness being the end and object to be kept constantly in view, the word Utility did not necessarily bring with it felicity as its associate- It can hardly be without inter est to trace the influences of the Greatest-Hap piness Principle upon Mr Bentham's philosophy, from the period when it first occupied his seri- 288 HISTORY OF THE ous thoughts, until it became the master-key which he applied to unlock all the intricacies of moral and political science. It was indeed his directing post, which he consulted in all the walks of life, whether pub lic or private ; the oracle, to whose voice he unhesitatingly and on all occasions deferred, both in his individual capacity, when seeking guidance for his own steps, and as one of the community endeavoring to mark out for others the path of popular wisdom and virtue. In every part of the field of thought and action he invoked its aid and counsel : he appealed to it for its laws, and for the reasons of those laws, and registered its responses for the use and government of his fellow men. To himself he suggested it, and to others he recommended it, not only as an end to be pro posed, but as a means of attaining that end, and as a motive to impel men to its pursuit, It was to him a storehouse of arguments, objects, instruments, and rewards. He did not leave his purpose clouded in a vague, misty and general phraseology, but drew forth from the regions of happiness and misery all those pleasures and pains of which happiness and misery are composed, and of which man's nature is susceptible. In the pleasures which the human being can enjoy, in the pains from GREATEST-HAPPINESS PRINCIPLE. 289 which the human being can be exempted, he found the elements of the science he taught. To calculate their number, to weigh their value, to estimate their results, was the object in which he was perpetually engaged; and to ga ther up the greatest possible quantity of felicity for every man, whether by alleviating suffering or increasing enjoyments, was the great busi ness of his life. These pains and pleasures when applied to the business of government, whether legislative or administrative, are but so many elementary parts of the stock employable by rulers in the manufacture of human happiness. The history of the Utilitarian Principle, is the history of contributions to the stock of happi ness; it is the history of what has been done, from time to time, to improve and perfect the operations of which enjoyment is the result. The finished work is felicity, and every instru ment and every workman assisting in its pro duction, or producing it in a more complete and enduring shape, is intitled to the honor of co operation or of discovery. Those literary works which have led to the efficient application of the instruments of happi ness, — those instructions by which advances have been made from the speculative and unem ployed principle, towards its use in the business VOL. i. u 290 HISTORY OF THE of life, must be considered among the most im portant auxiliaries in the furtherance of the triumphs of felicity. The earliest known mention of the principle is to be found in the 3rd Satire of Horace (book first), written a few years before the birth of Christ. The poet speaks of the opinions held by the Stoics, that all misdeeds (peccata} stand on the same level in the scale of ill desert, or rather should be visited with the same amount of blame, and thus pursues the topic — Queis paria esse fere placuit peccata, laborant Quum ventum ad verum est : sensus moresque repugnant ; Atque ipsa utilitasjusti prope mater et PJNESS PRINCIPLE. 311 were not strong enough, nor did he desire they should be strong enough, to endure the light from the orb of utilitarian felicity. Insincere himself, and the bold, oft-declared advocate of insincerity, what could be expected from his courage or his virtue? Over his bottle, those who knew him, knew that he was the self- avowed lover and champion of corruption, rich enough to keep an equipage, but not (as he himself declared) to 'keep a conscience.' For the remaining twenty years of his life, his book was the text-book of the universities ; but he left the utilitarian controversy as he found it; not even honoring the all-beneficent principle with an additional passing notice, It was in the year 1789, that the ' Introduc tion to the Principles of Morals and Legislation' appeared. Here, for the first time, are pains and pleasures separately defined, and regularly grouped; and the classification and definition of them is so complete for all ordinary purposes of moral and legislative investigation, that Mr Bentham, in after life, found little to modify or to add to in the list. By the side of the pains and the pleasures, the corresponding motives are brought to view, and a clear and determinate idea attached to the springs of action by show ing their separate operation. And, moreover, the author uncovers and sifts that phraseology which 312 HISTORY OF THE has done so much mischief in the field of right and wrong by the judgment of motives, instead of the judgment of conduct, so that the same motive is frequently spoken of in terms opposed to and incompatible with one another. Sometimes the eulogistic form is adopted, to convey sentiments of approbation ; sometimes the dyslogistic, to communicate sentiments of disapprobation ; sometimes the neutral, to avoid the expression of either praise or blame ; but in all cases these irrelevant and delusive adjuncts serve to bewil der inquiry, and to distort truth. Of this truly extraordinary and philosophical volume, it has chanced to the writer to hear the opinion of several of the most acute and distinguished men of the present day (not of the Utilitarian school) who, after a discussion as to what literary work ought to be considered the most remarkable intellectual production of the last century, unanimously decided that the ' Intro duction to the Principles of Morals and Legis lation T was intitled to that honor. In the later years of Mr Bentham's life he was far from deeming it complete. He had not taken man's interests and man's desires into his list, and he employed the phraseology of utility instead of that of happiness. The first part of Chrestomathia was published in 1810, the second part in the year following. GREATEST-HAPPINESS PRINCIPLE. 313 Its principal object was, to bring together the several branches of art and science, and to exhibit their conduciveness to happiness; to point out their relationship to each other through this their common property, and to give the whole that direction which, as a result, should produce the maximization of felicity. It was as early as 17G9 that Bentham's mind was occupied with this topic. Even then he fancied that happiness might be made the common trunk to support all the branches of know ledge, forming together a perfect encyclopae dical tree. In Lord Bacon's writings he found planted the pristine tree ; it was in some sort improved by D'Alembert ; but neither the English nor the French philosopher had taken any notice of that most useful of properties, to which all arts and sciences tend, and to which alone they are indebted for any value they possess. The trees they sought to plant had, however, never taken root, and, in the presence of Bentham's nobler production, must be considered as mere cumberers of the ground. It was in 1817 that 'The Table of the Springs of Action' appeared. The purpose of the author was to facilitate comparisons of and observations on the mutual relations between pains and pleasures, inducements or motives, desires and interests. lie endeavored to make 314 HISTORY OF THE the list complete of all the elements that influ ence conduct. While, in his previous writings, pains, pleasures, and motives had been the principal topics of inquiry, Mr Bentham added, on this occasion, the corresponding desires and interests, proposing, as a means of consistency and completeness, the designation of each inte rest by a particular name. Helvetius had in some cases attached names to interests, and Mr Bentham proposed to perfect the nomen clature, and to assist the association between all the points of comparison, by presenting the topics in a tabular form. To these Tables he subjoined notes, explaining and giving deter minate expression to other psychological terms, such as passions, virtues, vices, moral good, moral evil, and so forth, showing their connec tion with the objects displayed in the Tables. Though the Greatest-Happiness Principle was constantly in view— the now all-ruling influ ence in Mr Bentham's mind — no reference is made to it by name in ' The Springs of Action/ This volume is, however, the evidence of a great progress in utilitarian philosophy. The operations of motives on conduct had been most lucidly explained in the « Introduction to Morals and Legislation/ Motives, the source of action in all its modifications, are brought into association with all the pleasures and pains GREATEST-HAPPINESS PRINCIPLE. 315 they are able to influence : a motive, in fact, being only the fear of some pain from a certain mode of action, which pain the will is urged to avoid, or the hope of a pleasure which the will is urged to create. The ' Springs of Ac tion' did for interests what the * Introduction* did for motives ; they also drew the distinction between motives and desires. To each desire Bentham attached the adjectives by which the desire had been qualified, in order to suit the purpose of the speakers or writers who had occasion to refer to it, either in terms of praise or blame, the very same desire having ordinarily three designations, one laudatory, one vitupe- ratory, and the other neutral. Having observed the prodigious extent to which these collateral adjuncts are in use, as instruments of delusion and deception, espe cially in the hands of interested deceivers, it occurred to him that it would be a useful ser vice to mark out, and, as it were, give warning of the characteristic difference between the three classes, by means of appropriate deno minations. Accordingly, for the designation of the cas^ in which, to the idea of desire the idea of disapprobation, as existing in the mind of him who is speaking of it, is attached, he employed the epithet dyslogistic; as a synonyme, he might have added disapprobative: and, for 316 HISTORY OF THE the designation of the case in which, to the idea of desire, the idea of approbation, as exist ing in the mind of him who is speaking of it, is attached, he employed the epithet eulogistic ; as a synonyme, he might have added appro- bative. Mr Bentham has mentioned, that, in all his pursuits and inquiries, one idea was constantly operating on his mind. !f Bacon, with his ' Experimentalize ! ' was justly honored for doing more than any man who had preceded him, for the diffusion of the philosophy of physics, Ben tham, with his ever-present maxim — 'Observe!1 — is intitled to the first rank among those who have successfully labored for the advancement of the philosophy of morals. The phenomena of the material world, not only as they present themselves, but also as they can be made to present themselves, together with the relations in the way of cause and effect that appear to have place between them, may, without reserve (so as injury to persons and things be avoided) be taken for subjects of experiment as well as observation, when applied to the material world : in the case of moral and political science, the proper subject-matters of observation are pains and pleasures, as they respectively result from the several modifications of which human con GREATEST-HAPPINESS PRINCIPLE. 317 duct, or say human agency, is susceptible. Without reserve, these may be taken for sub ject-matters of observation : but, not without great reserve and caution, for subjects of expe riment ; especially in the case where the insti- tutor of the experiment is any other person than the sovereign, or a person or persons con stituted for the purpose, in authority under him. Accordingly, it is by the observation of the occasions on which, and shapes in which pain and pleasure result from the modes of agency respectively productive of them — pains more especially — that Mr Bentham ascertains the quantity and quality of the applications necessary as remedies for the evils which actions of the maleficent class bring in their train : and while the graphic pencil is engaged in the delineation of their respective qualities or forms, — scales, with weights and measures, are at the same time to be kept employed in giving intimation of their respective quantities. In the application of legislation to the pur poses of life, the legislator has only the choice of evils. There can be no government without coercion ; no coercion without suffering ; and, separately considered, that coercion must be an evil. The punitory functions of government consist in the application of that evil to the individual misdoers, for the purpose of obtain- 318 HISTORY OF THE ing, in the interests of the community, an exemption from greater evils, or a production of pleasures of greater value than the sufferings created by its coercive interposition. It is thus that the Greatest-Happiness Prin ciple brings the legislator into the field of particular pains and pleasures, and the first emanation of that principle is the ' disappoint ment-prevention/ or, as Mr Bentham more habitually called it, the 'non-disappointment* principle. Upon this the laws of property have their sole foundation ; for if no disappointment were felt — no pains suffered from the loss of property — no demand would there be for penal visitation in cases of the violation of what are called the rights of property. Let disappoint ment, as far as possible, be prevented. Why pre vented ? Because disappointment cannot have place without pain. Inseparably connected with the idea of disappointment is that of expectation — of agreeable expectation. The disappointment prevents the expectation from being realized. The legislator's business is to protect the subject from the sufferings of that disappointment. An observation made to Mr Bentham by Lady Holland produced a great impression upon him. She said that his doctrine of utility put a veto upon pleasure ; while he had been GREATEST-HAPPINESS PRINCIPLE. 319 fancying that pleasure never found so valuable and influential an ally as the principle of utility. It was clear, therefore, that the word ' utility* not only failed in communicating to other minds the ideas which Bentham attached to it, but that to some minds it communicated ideas wholly different and opposed to them. And true it i*, that unless the Greatest-Happiness Principle be recognized as the end, the doctrine of utility might be represented as useful to some other end. And if the pursuit of pleasure were assumed as worthy of disapprobation, utility would teach abstention from that pursuit. Dissatisfaction, therefore, with utilitarian phra seology, gradually increased in Bentham's mind. The phrase ' greatest happiness of the great est number' was first employed by Mr Bentham in 1822, in his ' Codification Proposal.' Every suggestion there put forward is made to turn upon the requirements of the ' greatest happi ness of the greatest number.' In this work, happiness, utility, pains and pleasures, are con stantly introduced for the purposes of explain ing one another ; and the augmentation of the felicity of all, by the increase of pleasures, and the exemption from pains, is the constantly pre sent theme. In our language, and in every known language, 320 HISTORY OF THE the advance of philosophy is greatly retarded by the want of appropriate expressions. If with the word ' utility * the idea of happiness could have been habitually and irrevocably associated, ' utilitarianism' would have conveniently repre sented the Greatest-Happiness Principle, and * utilitarians3 its advocates and supporters. And hitherto it has been almost necessary to use the terms which have indeed received a certain currency. Bentham once thought of proposing the employment of the word Eudaimonology, to represent the utilitarian doctrines, and Eudai- monologians its professors. To those acquainted with Greek the meaning would be sufficiently obvious ; but that acquaintance is so rare, that he did not venture to recommend the terms to general adoption. Besides, custom must be departed from in not rendering the word Euda- monology ; and in such a shape umbrage might be given to men of pious minds, who would possibly associate with it the idea of a doctrine, art, or science, of which devils were the sub ject. Hereafter, when the principle shall have made new conquests in other lands, and especi ally in those, the roots of whose languages are Latin, some terms may be found making way to general acceptance. Fettcitism, or Feliritarian- isnit — Felicitists, or Felicitarians, may then put forward their claim. The word 'felicity' has GREATEST-HAPPINESS PRINCIPLE. 321 already two conjugates, to felicitate, and felt* citous* The increase of the number of conju* gates would be of important asvsistance to lan guage; but for our purpose the idea of ' greatest* is needful, and the Felicity-maximizing princi ple will, perhaps, be found the most convenient of all the terms hitherto employed. The Gothic branch of our language unfortu nately does not lend itself to the wants of the utilitarian. There is no making one word of * Greatest Happiness;' still more difficult is it to extract from its roots the substitutes for those conjugates which the Latin will supply. The antagonist to the felicity-maximizing is, the ipse-dixit principle, and there is no reason why the ipse-dixit root should not produce all the branches necessary to discourse, — as ipse- divitists, and ipse-dixitism. It is scarcely out of place, by the way, to state here, in answer to those who have so fre- quently animadverted on Mr Bentham's unusual terms, that there is no topic on which his mind was more habitually occupied than in the search of fit terms to convey his ideas. No man was ever more impressed with the importance of appropriate nomenclature, as the necessary instrument for logical reasoning, for introducing and disseminating correct ideas. It was the ambition of a Roman emperor to plant a word VOL. i. Y 322 HISTORY OF THE which should be allowed by after times to grow, Two words, at least, have been planted by Bentham, and adopted into our language, — the adjective international, the noun codification, with its conjugates, to codify and codifiers; and though he can hardly be said to have introduced the verbs to maximize and to minimize, with their correspondent nouns, he has certainly given them that currency, and attached to them that value, which afford the assurance of their escap ing the doom of oblivion. But even the words which are every day in the mouth of every man are constantly employed without any accurate understanding of their precise or real meaning. Virtue and vice, justice and injustice, what are they ? By nothing but in connection with the Greatest-Happiness Prin ciple can any clear or useful application be made of them, or any of them. Whenever, indeed, they are employed, there is some refer ence, implied or expressed, to one of these prin ciples, — the Greatest-Happiness Principle, or the principle directly opposed to it, that is, the ascetic principle, or the dogmatic principle of ipse-dixitism. For the end in view, the stand ard of right and wrong must be either happi ness or unhappiness, or else some opinion which is put forward as sufficient in itself to deter mine the standard. The appellative of ipse- GREATEST-HAPPINESS PRINCIPLE. 323 dixitism is not a new one ; it comes down to us from an antique and high authority, —it is the principle recognised (so Cicero informs us) by the disciples of Pythagoras. Ipse (he, the mas ter, Pythagoras), ipse dixit, — he has said it ; the master has said that it is so ; therefore, say the disciples of the illustrious sage, therefore so it is. When the 'Introduction to Morals and Legis lation ' was published, Bentham imagined that the principle of sympathy and antipathy was to be considered the groundwork of one of the theories of morals. In after life, he discovered that this was only the dogmatic, or ipse-dixit principle divided into two branches : — the branch of sympathy applying reward, that of antipathy, punishment ; but, wherever disasso ciated from the Greatest-Happiness Principle, being really nothing but the authority of the ipse-dixit doctrine. The principle of caprice was the appellative that afterwards occurred to, and has been em ployed by him for the designation of that branch of the ipse-dixit principle which applies to the civil, or non-penal branch of law, including every portion not comprised within the denomi nation of the penal ; the civil, or non-penal, over which, in his view of the matter, the non- disappointment principle presides. To return to virtue and vice. By virtue, 324 HISTORY OF THE under the direction of the Greatest-Happiness Principle, is understood that line of conduct and correspondent disposition, which is conducive to happiness : by vice, that which is conducive to unhappiness. In the case of the virtue one addition, however, and that productive of a limitative effect, requires to be made ; this is that of the sort of action denominated virtuous, the exercise requires more or less of self- denial : that is to say, of a sacrifice made of the present good, whether pleasure or exemption from pain, to some greater good to come. For keeping the position in question within the pale of truth, this limitative adjunct is altogether indispensable. And the evidence that it is so is irresistible. Among the actions, by the exercise of which the existence of the individual is con- tinued, and among them of those by which pleasure is experienced, or pain averted and excluded, small is the proportion of those by which virtue, in any shape, can with propriety be said to be exercised. Why? Because, in the exercise made of them, no self-denial, no sacrifice of the present to the future good is made. Thus it is, for example, with the plea sures of sense in general. But here comes in an objection. Suppose a man to have his appetites and desires of all sorts in such complete subjection, that, in the GREATEST-HAPPINESS PRINCIPLE. 325 sacrifice of the lesser present to the greater future good, no uneasiness is experienced, nothing that can be called self -denial is prac tised. Of such a man will you say, that, in his mental frame virtue is on a lower level, in the scale of perfection, than in the case of one in whom the contest between the lesser present and greater future good, or, according to Dean Swift's emblem, the game of leap-frog between flesh and spirit, is continually renewed ? No, assuredly. But for this not less true is it, that to the applying with propriety to a man's habit and disposition the appellatives virtue and virtu ous, the supposition of the existence of reluc tance and self-denial in the character of an ac companiment of an ingredient in the habit is indispensable ; at the time in question no such unpleasant sensation has place, but at some anterior point of time it had place ; only in the intervening space of time it has been gradually worn away ; as a laborious exertion by long habit becomes pleasurable. The Greatest-Happiness Principle is not only attacked by prinriplr.s oprnly mid proflwt'illy opposed to it ; it has had to suffer from covert and influential usurpers of its name and authority ; and from such sources it has perhaps been most injured. Reference has been made and homage paid to it by principles 326 HISTORY OF THE which have claimed alliance with it, while they have, in fact, been only subordinate to ipse- dixitism. This has been too ofjen the position of the preachers of ' Justice, '—men, who, under the cloak and covering of an attractive title, have generally strung together their directions precepts, mandates — call them what you will — saying to every body who will listen, ' Do so and so, for this is what is required by justice/ Two assumptions are here, and both are represen tatives of the ipse-dixit system: — first, that justice is the proper and sufficient standard of reference ; and second, that this which you are required to do is dictated by justice, — assump tions (need it be said ?) both unsupported by argument, both gratuitous and dogmatical. When Mr Godwin took ' Political Justice ' for the title of his well-known work, he committed an act of insubordination, not to say rebellion, or high treason, against the sovereignty of the only legitimate, all-ruling principle. Justice is subservient to the Greatest-Happi ness Principle, or it is not : its dictates teach the minimization of misery, and the maximiza tion of happiness, or they do not. If they do, and as far as they do, they are in accordance with that principle, and they represent it. But, suppose their dictates differ, suppose there is dissonance, hostility between the two, GREATEST-HAPPINESS PRINCIPLE. 327 which is to succumb ? Justice or happiness,— the end or the means ? In order to a proper intelligence and applica tion of the meaning of the word justice, it must be divided into its two branches, civil and penal ; for nothing can be more vague, obscure, and unsatisfactory, than the ideas attached to the word justice, as it is ordinarily applied. Civil justice is the recognition of proprietary rights in all their shapes, whether as objects of desire, or of possessed value. To 'invade the proprietor of them in his expectations or pos sessions, or to deprive him of them, is to create in his mind the pains of disappointment, — pains, which the felicity-maximizing principle requires to be averted. This disappointment-preventing principle stands second in importance to the happiness-creating principle. The penal branch of civil justice presents a different aspect. Its purpose is to minimize wrongs. Its means are preventive, suppres- sive, satisfactive, and punitive. It is only in as far as wrongs are the cause of unhappiness that there is any demand for penalties. To reduce the aggregate of wrongs, and thereby the sources of suffering growing out of them, and to do this at the least cost of pain, is the de mand of that justice which is in alliance with the Greatest-Happiness Principle. But under OOQ *3*3 -HrSTORY'OT THE- -i « /. .Ut. the Tiame of justice verjr : different objects, and those to be accomplished by very different ends, are frequently proposed,1 In the later years of Mr Bentham's life the phrase 'Greatest happiness of the greatest num ber ' appeared, on a closer scrutiny, to be want ing in that clearness and correctness which had originally recommended it to his notice and adoption. And these are the reasons for his change of opinion, given in his own words: — ' Be the community in question what it may, ' divide it into two unequal parts ; call one of 'them the majority, the other the minority; lay ' out of the account the feelings of the minority ; ' include in the account no feelings but those of 'the majority, — you will find, that to the aggre- ' gate stock of the happiness of the community, 'loss, not profit, is the result of the operation. ' Of this proposition the truth will be the more 4 palpable, the greater the ratio of the number of 'the minority to that of the majority; in other 'words, the less the difference between the two ' unequal parts; and suppose the undivided parts ' equal, the quantity of the error will then be at * its maximum. ' Number of the majority suppose 2001, ' number of the minority, 2000. Suppose, in 'the first place, the stock of happiness in such ' sort divided, that by every one of the 4001 an GREATEST-HAPPINESS PRINCIPLE. 329 ' equal portion of happiness shall be possessed. 4 Take now from every one of the 2000 his share ' of happiness, and divide it any how among the ' 2001 : instead of augmentation, vast is the ' diminution you will find to be the result. The ' feelings of the minority being, by the supposi- 4 tion, laid intirely out of the account (for such, 4 in its enlarged form, is the import of the propo- 4 sition), the vacuum thus left may, instead of 'remaining a vacuum, be filled with unhappiness, 4 positive suffering, in magnitude, intensity, and * duration taken together, the greatest which it is ' in the power of human nature to endure. 4 Take from your 2000, and give to your 2001 ' all the happiness you find your 2000 in pos- 4 session of : insert, in the room of the happiness ' you have taken out, unhappiness in as large 4 a quantity as the receptacle will contain : to ' the aggregate amount of the happiness pos- 4 sessed by the 4001 taken together, will the 4 result be net profit ? on the contrary, the whole 4 profit will have given place to loss. How so ? ' because so it is, that such is the nature of the * receptacle, the quantity of unhappiness it is 4 capable of containing, during any given portion ' of time, is greater than the quantity of hap- 4 piness. 4 At the outset, place your 4001 in a state of ' perfect equality, in respect of the means, VOL. i. x 330 HISTORY OF THE 'or say, instruments of happiness, and in par- ' ticular, power and opulence : every one of them 'in a state of equal liberty; every one indepen- ' dent of every other : every one of them pos- ' sessing an equal portion of money and money's ' worth : in this state it is that you find them, '.Taking in hand now your 2000, reduce them 'to a state of slavery, and, no matter in what ' proportions of the slaves thus constituted, divide 'the whole number with such, their property, 'among your 2001; the operation performed, 'of the happiness of what number will an 'augmentation be the result? The question ' answers itself. * Were it otherwise, note now the practical 'application that would be to be made of it in ' the British Isles. In Great Britain, take the 'whole body of the Roman Catholics, make 'slaves of them, and divide them in any pro- ' portion, them and their progeny, among the 'whole body of the Protestants. In Ireland, ' take the whole body of the Protestants, and ' divide them, in like manner, among the whole ' body of the Roman Catholics.' The danger of putting forward any proposi tion as a leading principle, other than that which would maximize felicity, consists in this —that if it coincide with the greater principle it is supererogatory; if it do not coincide, it is GREATEST-HAZINESS PRINCIPLE. 331 pernicious. Any principle that is not subordi nate to it may be opposed to it, either diametri cally or collaterally. The ascetic principle, if all-comprehensive and consistent, may be evi denced as one of direct opposition, — the ipse- dixit principles of all sorts may be ranked among the indirect opponents. Qui non sub me contra me. * He who is not under me is against me/ may be said with figurative or meta phorical truth by the Greatest-Happiness Prin ciple, and with literal truth by every one of its partisans. And let not this declaration be taken as the result of arrogance of disposition : it grows out of the nature of things, and the ne cessities of the case. Let it not be considered to bespeak unkindness towards any advocate of the opposite opinions, for such unkindness is neither its necessary, nor even its natural accompaniment. END OF THE FIRST VOLUME. LONDON: C. ANT W. HKYNKLL, PRINTERS, LITTLE PUI-TENEY STREKT, HAYMARKET. ERRATA TO VOL, I. PAGE 26 for ' obteperous/ read 'obstreperous.' 53 four lines from bottom, dele ' be/ 89 for * remunatory,' read ' remuoeratory.1 143 first line, for « garding,' read * regarding.' 167 5 lines from bottom, for « the interest in a family/ retd ' the interest Jelt in a family,' 1 69 10 lines from top, for « these thoughts,' read ' their thoughts. 204 13 lines from top, for ' sactiou ' read • sanction.' 236 6 lines from top, for* in,* read « for.' ~